Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 11 de 11
Filter
2.
J Am Acad Psychiatry Law ; 38(2): 174-86, 2010.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-20542936

ABSTRACT

The confession of a criminal defendant serves as a prosecutor's most compelling piece of evidence during trial. Courts must preserve a defendant's constitutional right to a fair trial while upholding the judicial interests of presenting competent and reliable evidence to the jury. When a defendant seeks to challenge the validity of that confession through expert testimony, the prosecution often contests the admissibility of the expert's opinion. Depending on the content and methodology of the expert's opinion, testimony addressing the phenomenon of false confessions may or may not be admissible. This article outlines the scientific and epistemological bases of expert testimony on false confession, notes the obstacles facing its admissibility, and provides guidance to the expert in formulating opinions that will reach the judge or jury. We review the 2006 New Jersey Superior Court decision in State of New Jersey v. George King to illustrate what is involved in the admissibility of false-confession testimony and use the case as a starting point in developing a best-practice approach to working in this area.


Subject(s)
Deception , Expert Testimony/legislation & jurisprudence , Homicide/legislation & jurisprudence , Prisoners/legislation & jurisprudence , Truth Disclosure , Antisocial Personality Disorder/diagnosis , Antisocial Personality Disorder/psychology , Borderline Personality Disorder/diagnosis , Borderline Personality Disorder/psychology , Coercion , Defense Mechanisms , Fantasy , Guilt , Homicide/psychology , Humans , Insanity Defense , Male , Personality Disorders/diagnosis , Personality Disorders/psychology , Prisoners/psychology , United States
3.
J Am Acad Psychiatry Law ; 44(2): 226-35, 2016 Jun.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27236179

ABSTRACT

Section 7.3 of the code of ethics of the American Psychiatric Association (APA) cautions psychiatrists against making public statements about public figures whom they have not formally evaluated. The APA's concern is to safeguard the public perception of psychiatry as a scientific and credible profession. The ethic is that diagnostic terminology and theory should not be used for speculative or ad hominem attacks that promote the interests of the individual physician or for political and ideological causes. However, the Goldwater Rule presents conflicting problems. These include the right to speak one's conscience regarding concerns about the psychological stability of high office holders and competing considerations regarding one's role as a private citizen versus that as a professional figure. Furthermore, the APA's proscription on diagnosis without formal interview can be questioned, since third-party payers, expert witnesses in law cases, and historical psychobiographers make diagnoses without conducting formal interviews. Some third-party assessments are reckless, but do not negate legitimate reasons for providing thoughtful education to the public and voicing psychiatric concerns as acts of conscience. We conclude that the Goldwater Rule was an excessive organizational response to what was clearly an inflammatory and embarrassing moment for American psychiatry.


Subject(s)
Mental Disorders/diagnosis , Psychiatry/ethics , Societies, Medical , Guidelines as Topic , Humans , United States
4.
Curr Opin Psychiatry ; 18(6): 659-63, 2005 Nov.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-16639092

ABSTRACT

PURPOSE OF REVIEW: Psychiatry is increasingly aware of its own conceptual foundations and the role that philosophy plays in shaping research and practice. This growing awareness is especially prominent in the area of psychopathology, where both philosophers and psychiatrists are actively investigating the basic assumptions and values that influence the science. RECENT FINDINGS: There is growing attention to the role of values in understanding both the concepts of psychopathology, and the philosophical assumptions that underlie research strategies for studying it. Provocative work is being done to clarify the concept of 'mental disorder', to identify the influence of values in the classification and diagnosis of psychopathology, and to use values to argue for comprehensive research efforts. Psychometricians increasingly question the interplay between the philosophical theory and empirical study of psychopathology. SUMMARY: Both epistemology and value theory are central to the conceptualization and research of psychopathology. This prominence is recognized not only by philosophers and psychiatrists interested in philosophy, but by investigators who must grapple with the mutual influence of philosophical concepts and research methods. By making our philosophical views explicit and maintaining our awareness of them, we are well poised to develop and question both our philosophical and our research methods in meaningful ways.

5.
Philos Ethics Humanit Med ; 7: 3, 2012 Jan 13.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22243994

ABSTRACT

In face of the multiple controversies surrounding the DSM process in general and the development of DSM-5 in particular, we have organized a discussion around what we consider six essential questions in further work on the DSM. The six questions involve: 1) the nature of a mental disorder; 2) the definition of mental disorder; 3) the issue of whether, in the current state of psychiatric science, DSM-5 should assume a cautious, conservative posture or an assertive, transformative posture; 4) the role of pragmatic considerations in the construction of DSM-5; 5) the issue of utility of the DSM - whether DSM-III and IV have been designed more for clinicians or researchers, and how this conflict should be dealt with in the new manual; and 6) the possibility and advisability, given all the problems with DSM-III and IV, of designing a different diagnostic system. Part I of this article will take up the first two questions. With the first question, invited commentators express a range of opinion regarding the nature of psychiatric disorders, loosely divided into a realist position that the diagnostic categories represent real diseases that we can accurately name and know with our perceptual abilities, a middle, nominalist position that psychiatric disorders do exist in the real world but that our diagnostic categories are constructs that may or may not accurately represent the disorders out there, and finally a purely constructivist position that the diagnostic categories are simply constructs with no evidence of psychiatric disorders in the real world. The second question again offers a range of opinion as to how we should define a mental or psychiatric disorder, including the possibility that we should not try to formulate a definition. The general introduction, as well as the introductions and conclusions for the specific questions, are written by James Phillips, and the responses to commentaries are written by Allen Frances.


Subject(s)
Concept Formation , Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders , Mental Disorders/classification , Mental Disorders/diagnosis , Humans
6.
Philos Ethics Humanit Med ; 7: 8, 2012 Jul 05.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22512887

ABSTRACT

In face of the multiple controversies surrounding the DSM process in general and the development of DSM-5 in particular, we have organized a discussion around what we consider six essential questions in further work on the DSM. The six questions involve: 1) the nature of a mental disorder; 2) the definition of mental disorder; 3) the issue of whether, in the current state of psychiatric science, DSM-5 should assume a cautious, conservative posture or an assertive, transformative posture; 4) the role of pragmatic considerations in the construction of DSM-5; 5) the issue of utility of the DSM--whether DSM-III and IV have been designed more for clinicians or researchers, and how this conflict should be dealt with in the new manual; and 6) the possibility and advisability, given all the problems with DSM-III and IV, of designing a different diagnostic system. Part I of this article took up the first two questions. Part II will take up the second two questions. Question 3 deals with the question as to whether DSM-V should assume a conservative or assertive posture in making changes from DSM-IV. That question in turn breaks down into discussion of diagnoses that depend on, and aim toward, empirical, scientific validation, and diagnoses that are more value-laden and less amenable to scientific validation. Question 4 takes up the role of pragmatic consideration in a psychiatric nosology, whether the purely empirical considerations need to be tempered by considerations of practical consequence. As in Part 1 of this article, the general introduction, as well as the introductions and conclusions for the specific questions, are written by James Phillips, and the responses to commentaries are written by Allen Frances.


Subject(s)
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders , Mental Disorders/diagnosis , Philosophy, Medical , Psychiatry/methods , Psychometrics/methods , Ethics, Medical , Humans , Mental Disorders/psychology , Psychiatry/instrumentation , Psychometrics/instrumentation
7.
Philos Ethics Humanit Med ; 7: 9, 2012 May 23.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22621419

ABSTRACT

In face of the multiple controversies surrounding the DSM process in general and the development of DSM-5 in particular, we have organized a discussion around what we consider six essential questions in further work on the DSM. The six questions involve: 1) the nature of a mental disorder; 2) the definition of mental disorder; 3) the issue of whether, in the current state of psychiatric science, DSM-5 should assume a cautious, conservative posture or an assertive, transformative posture; 4) the role of pragmatic considerations in the construction of DSM-5; 5) the issue of utility of the DSM - whether DSM-III and IV have been designed more for clinicians or researchers, and how this conflict should be dealt with in the new manual; and 6) the possibility and advisability, given all the problems with DSM-III and IV, of designing a different diagnostic system. Part 1 of this article took up the first two questions. Part 2 took up the second two questions. Part 3 now deals with Questions 5 & 6. Question 5 confronts the issue of utility, whether the manual design of DSM-III and IV favors clinicians or researchers, and what that means for DSM-5. Our final question, Question 6, takes up a concluding issue, whether the acknowledged problems with the earlier DSMs warrants a significant overhaul of DSM-5 and future manuals. As in Parts 1 & 2 of this article, the general introduction, as well as the introductions and conclusions for the specific questions, are written by James Phillips, and the responses to commentaries are written by Allen Frances.


Subject(s)
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders , Mental Disorders/diagnosis , Philosophy, Medical , Psychiatry/methods , Psychometrics/methods , Humans , Mental Disorders/psychology , Psychiatry/instrumentation , Psychometrics/instrumentation
8.
Philos Ethics Humanit Med ; 7: 14, 2012 Dec 18.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23249629

ABSTRACT

In the conclusion to this multi-part article I first review the discussions carried out around the six essential questions in psychiatric diagnosis - the position taken by Allen Frances on each question, the commentaries on the respective question along with Frances' responses to the commentaries, and my own view of the multiple discussions. In this review I emphasize that the core question is the first - what is the nature of psychiatric illness - and that in some manner all further questions follow from the first. Following this review I attempt to move the discussion forward, addressing the first question from the perspectives of natural kind analysis and complexity analysis. This reflection leads toward a view of psychiatric disorders - and future nosologies - as far more complex and uncertain than we have imagined.


Subject(s)
Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders , Mental Disorders/diagnosis , Humans , Mental Disorders/classification , Reproducibility of Results , Terminology as Topic
10.
Theor Med Bioeth ; 31(1): 93-105, 2010 Feb.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-20237853

ABSTRACT

The mental health recovery movement promotes patient self-determination and opposes coercive psychiatric treatment. While it has made great strides towards these ends, its rhetoric impairs its political efficacy. We illustrate how psychiatry can share recovery values and yet appear to violate them. In certain criminal proceedings, for example, forensic psychiatrists routinely argue that persons with mental illness who have committed crimes are not full moral agents. Such arguments align with the recovery movement's aim of providing appropriate treatment and services for people with severe mental illness, but contradict its fundamental principle of self-determination. We suggest that this contradiction should be addressed with some urgency, and we recommend a multidisciplinary collaborative effort involving ethics, law, psychiatry, and social policy to address this and other ethical questions that arise as the United States strives to implement recovery-oriented programs.


Subject(s)
Bioethics , Character , Community Psychiatry , Criminals/psychology , Dangerous Behavior , Forensic Psychiatry , Mental Disorders/psychology , Mental Disorders/rehabilitation , Morals , Personal Autonomy , Beneficence , Commitment of Mentally Ill/legislation & jurisprudence , Commitment of Mentally Ill/standards , Commitment of Mentally Ill/trends , Community Mental Health Services , Community Psychiatry/standards , Community Psychiatry/trends , Decision Making , Forensic Psychiatry/standards , Forensic Psychiatry/trends , Humans , Interdisciplinary Communication , Jurisprudence , Knowledge , Mental Competency , Patient Advocacy , Physician-Patient Relations/ethics , Public Policy/legislation & jurisprudence , Public Policy/trends , Punishment , Recovery of Function , Self-Help Groups , Social Values , Terminology as Topic , United States
11.
Psychopathology ; 38(4): 166-70, 2005.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-16145267

ABSTRACT

To deal effectively with the understanding, description and classification of mental morbid conditions, we must address the intricate concept of disease, illness or disorder in mental health. To do so, one needs to consider biological, psychological and social frameworks. These levels of analysis can offer avenues for greater understanding of the bases of illness as well as better ways of formulating its description and classification. Conceptual, epistemological and empirical data analyses are relevant and necessary. All these efforts should be aimed at serving and advancing the main purposes of classification and diagnosis, the chief encompassing one being enhancement of clinical care and public health. Although no definition of mental disorder may strictly embrace every condition of concern, some flexible definitional guidelines within a biopsychosocial framework may be helpful for advancing psychiatric nosology.


Subject(s)
Mental Disorders/classification , Mental Disorders/diagnosis , Cultural Characteristics , Diagnosis, Differential , Humans , Neurosciences/trends , Psychophysiology , Terminology as Topic
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL