Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Mostrar: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 20 de 34
Filtrar
Más filtros

Banco de datos
País/Región como asunto
Tipo del documento
Intervalo de año de publicación
1.
Transfusion ; 63(5): 918-924, 2023 05.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36965173

RESUMEN

BACKGROUND AND OBJECTIVES: Convalescent COVID-19 plasma (CCP) was developed and used worldwide as a treatment option by supplying passive immunity. Adult studies suggest administering high-titer CCP early in the disease course of patients who are expected to be antibody-negative; however, pediatric experience is limited. We created a multi-institutional registry to characterize pediatric patients (<18 years) who received CCP and to assess the safety of this intervention. METHODS: A REDCap survey was distributed. The registry collected de-identified data including demographic information (age, gender, and underlying conditions), COVID-19 disease features and concurrent treatments, CCP transfusion and safety events, and therapy response. RESULTS: Ninety-five children received CCP: 90 inpatients and 5 outpatients, with a median age of 10.2 years (range 0-17.9). They were predominantly Latino/Hispanic and White. The most frequent underlying medical conditions were chronic respiratory disease, immunosuppression, obesity, and genetic syndromes. CCP was primarily given as a treatment (95%) rather than prophylaxis (5%). Median total plasma dose administered and transfusion rates were 5.0 ml/kg and 2.6 ml/kg/h, respectively. The transfusions were well-tolerated, with 3 in 115 transfusions reporting mild reactions. No serious adverse events were reported. Severity scores decreased significantly 7 days after CCP transfusion or at discharge. Eighty-five patients (94.4%) survived to hospital discharge. All five outpatients survived to 60 days. CONCLUSIONS: CCP was found to be safe and well-tolerated in children. CCP was frequently given concurrently with other COVID-19-directed treatments with improvement in clinical severity scores ≥7 days after CCP, but efficacy could not be evaluated in this study.


Asunto(s)
COVID-19 , Adulto , Humanos , Niño , Recién Nacido , Lactante , Preescolar , Adolescente , COVID-19/terapia , COVID-19/etiología , SARS-CoV-2 , Inmunización Pasiva/efectos adversos , Sueroterapia para COVID-19 , Transfusión Sanguínea
2.
J Pediatr Orthop ; 43(6): 400-406, 2023 Jul 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36922007

RESUMEN

BACKGROUND AND OBJECTIVES: Venous thromboembolic events (VTE) complicate acute hematogenous musculoskeletal infections (MSKIs) among hospitalized children. However, there is limited guidance for which specific MSKI patients are at the greatest VTE risk. This study aimed to identify VTE risk factors for children hospitalized with MSKIs. METHODS: A retrospective chart review was performed of children hospitalized with MSKIs at a single quaternary care pediatric hospital during a 9-year period. Patients with chronic MSKIs, non-hematogenous infections, or significant contributing comorbidities were excluded. Demographic and clinical characteristics were compared between patients with and without VTE using forward stepwise conditional multivariable logistic regression to identify VTE risk factors. RESULTS: Among 335 included patients, 7 (2.1%) developed a VTE. There was no difference in age, sex, or obesity rates for those with or without VTE. Patients with methicillin-resistant Staphylococcus aureus (MRSA) infections and/or critical illness were more likely to develop a VTE with summative adjusted odds ratios of 31.7 and 26.4, respectively. In addition, patients with VTEs had longer hospitalizations (median 4.7 vs. 12.8 d, P <0.001), longer courses of intravenous antimicrobials (median 3.7 vs. 13.5 d, P =0.001), and longer time to fever resolution (median 25.7 vs. 162 h, P =0.004). CONCLUSIONS: VTE prevalence among children with acute MSKIs is low. MRSA infection and critical illness significantly increase the risk for VTE development in these patients. Future prospective studies are needed to determine if VTEs in high-risk MSKI patients can be prevented.


Asunto(s)
Staphylococcus aureus Resistente a Meticilina , Tromboembolia Venosa , Humanos , Niño , Tromboembolia Venosa/epidemiología , Tromboembolia Venosa/etiología , Tromboembolia Venosa/prevención & control , Estudios Retrospectivos , Enfermedad Crítica , Factores de Riesgo
3.
Res Publica ; 29(2): 185-211, 2023.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37228851

RESUMEN

The widespread use of algorithms for prediction-based decisions urges us to consider the question of what it means for a given act or practice to be discriminatory. Building upon work by Kusner and colleagues in the field of machine learning, we propose a counterfactual condition as a necessary requirement on discrimination. To demonstrate the philosophical relevance of the proposed condition, we consider two prominent accounts of discrimination in the recent literature, by Lippert-Rasmussen and Hellman respectively, that do not logically imply our condition and show that they face important objections. Specifically, Lippert-Rasmussen's definition proves to be over-inclusive, as it classifies some acts or practices as discriminatory when they are not, whereas Hellman's account turns out to lack explanatory power precisely insofar as it does not countenance a counterfactual condition on discrimination. By defending the necessity of our counterfactual condition, we set the conceptual limits for justified claims about the occurrence of discriminatory acts or practices in society, with immediate applications to the ethics of algorithmic decision-making.

4.
Clin Infect Dis ; 75(1): e466-e472, 2022 08 24.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34549274

RESUMEN

BACKGROUND: The severe acute respiratory syndrome coronavirus 2 (SARS-CoV-2) pandemic has caused high inpatient mortality and morbidity throughout the world. COVID-19 convalescent plasma (CCP) has been utilized as a potential therapy for patients hospitalized with coronavirus disease 2019 (COVID-19) pneumonia. This study evaluated the outcomes of hospitalized patients with COVID-19 treated with CCP in a prospective, observational, multicenter trial. METHODS: From April through August 2020, hospitalized patients with COVID-19 at 16 participating hospitals in Colorado were enrolled and treated with CCP and compared with hospitalized patients with COVID-19 who were not treated with convalescent plasma. Plasma antibody levels were determined following the trial, given that antibody tests were not approved at the initiation of the trial. CCP-treated and untreated hospitalized patients with COVID-19 were matched using propensity scores followed by analysis for length of hospitalization and inpatient mortality. RESULTS: A total of 542 hospitalized patients with COVID-19 were enrolled at 16 hospitals across the region. A total of 468 hospitalized patients with COVID-19 were entered into propensity score matching with 188 patients matched for analysis in the CCP-treatment and control arms. Fine-Gray models revealed increased length of hospital stay in CCP-treated patients and no change in inpatient mortality compared with controls. In subgroup analysis of CCP-treated patients within 7 days of admission, there was no difference in length of hospitalization and inpatient mortality. CONCLUSIONS: These data show that treatment of hospitalized patients with COVID-19 treated with CCP did not significantly improve patient hospitalization length of stay or inpatient mortality.


Asunto(s)
COVID-19 , COVID-19/terapia , Humanos , Inmunización Pasiva/efectos adversos , Estudios Prospectivos , SARS-CoV-2 , Resultado del Tratamiento , Sueroterapia para COVID-19
5.
Pediatr Crit Care Med ; 23(12): e595-e600, 2022 12 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36194016

RESUMEN

OBJECTIVES: Cytokine release syndrome (CRS) is a potentially lethal toxicity associated with chimeric antigen receptor T cell therapy for pediatric acute lymphoblastic leukemia (ALL). Outcomes after critical illness due to severe CRS are poorly described. Our aim was to characterize critical illness outcomes across a multicenter cohort of PICU patients with ALL and CRS. DESIGN: Multicenter retrospective cohort study. SETTING: Twenty-one PICUs contributing data to Virtual Pediatric Systems, LLC (January 2020-December 2021). PATIENTS: PICU patients with ALL or unclassified leukemia and CRS. INTERVENTIONS: None. MEASUREMENTS AND MAIN RESULTS: We identified 55 patients; 34 (62%) were 12 years or older, 48 (87%) were admitted from a hospital inpatient ward, and 23 (42%) received advanced organ failure support or monitoring. Fifty-one survived to PICU discharge (93%) including 19 of 23 (83%) who received advanced organ failure support or monitoring defined as receipt of noninvasive or invasive ventilation, cardiopulmonary resuscitation, extracorporeal membrane oxygenation, continuous renal replacement therapy, or placement of a tracheostomy, arterial catheter, hemodialysis catheter, or intracranial catheter. Twelve patients (22%) received invasive ventilation, nine of whom survived to PICU discharge. Two of four patients who received continuous renal replacement therapy and one of three patients who required cardiopulmonary resuscitation survived to PICU discharge. Lengths of PICU stay were median 3.0 days (interquartile range, 1.4-7.8 d) among PICU survivors, 7.8 (5.4-11.1) among those receiving advanced organ failure support or monitoring, and 7.2 days (interquartile range, 2.9-14.7 d) among nonsurvivors. Of the 51 patients who survived to PICU discharge, 48 (94%) survived the hospitalization. CONCLUSIONS: PICU patients with CRS frequently received a high level of support, and the majority survived their PICU stay and hospitalization. Additional multicenter investigations of severe CRS are necessary to inform evidence-based practice.


Asunto(s)
Leucemia-Linfoma Linfoblástico de Células Precursoras , Receptores Quiméricos de Antígenos , Niño , Humanos , Lactante , Enfermedad Crítica/terapia , Unidades de Cuidado Intensivo Pediátrico , Estudios Retrospectivos , Síndrome de Liberación de Citoquinas , Estudios de Cohortes , Leucemia-Linfoma Linfoblástico de Células Precursoras/terapia , Tratamiento Basado en Trasplante de Células y Tejidos
6.
Ethics Inf Technol ; 23(3): 253-263, 2021.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34867077

RESUMEN

In this paper we argue that transparency of machine learning algorithms, just as explanation, can be defined at different levels of abstraction. We criticize recent attempts to identify the explanation of black box algorithms with making their decisions (post-hoc) interpretable, focusing our discussion on counterfactual explanations. These approaches to explanation simplify the real nature of the black boxes and risk misleading the public about the normative features of a model. We propose a new form of algorithmic transparency, that consists in explaining algorithms as an intentional product, that serves a particular goal, or multiple goals (Daniel Dennet's design stance) in a given domain of applicability, and that provides a measure of the extent to which such a goal is achieved, and evidence about the way that measure has been reached. We call such idea of algorithmic transparency "design publicity." We argue that design publicity can be more easily linked with the justification of the use and of the design of the algorithm, and of each individual decision following from it. In comparison to post-hoc explanations of individual algorithmic decisions, design publicity meets a different demand (the demand for impersonal justification) of the explainee. Finally, we argue that when models that pursue justifiable goals (which may include fairness as avoidance of bias towards specific groups) to a justifiable degree are used consistently, the resulting decisions are all justified even if some of them are (unavoidably) based on incorrect predictions. For this argument, we rely on John Rawls's idea of procedural justice applied to algorithms conceived as institutions.

7.
Pediatr Crit Care Med ; 21(12): e1148-e1151, 2020 12.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32639474

RESUMEN

OBJECTIVES: Perform a needs assessment by evaluating accuracy of PICU provider bedside ultrasound measurement of femoral vein diameter prior to utilization of the catheter-to-vein ratio for central venous catheter size selection. DESIGN: Prospective observational cohort study. SETTING: PICU within a quaternary care children's hospital. PATIENTS: PICU patients greater than 30 days and less than 6 years without a femoral central venous catheter. INTERVENTIONS: None. MEASUREMENTS AND MAIN RESULTS: Gold-standard femoral vein diameter measurements were made by a radiologist, sonographer, or bedside ultrasound expert. PICU providers then repeated the femoral vein diameter measurements, and results were compared by Bland-Altman analysis with a priori accuracy goal of limits of agreement ± 15%. Among recruited patients (n = 27), the median age was 1.1 years (interquartile range 0.5-2.3 yr), weight was 9.0 kg (interquartile range 7.0-11.5 kg), and reference femoral vein diameter was 0.36 cm (interquartile range 0.28-0.45 cm). Providers performed 148 femoral vein diameter measurements and did not meet goal accuracy when compared with the reference measurement with a bias of 4% (95% of limits of agreement -62% to 70%). A majority of patients would have a catheter-to-vein ratio greater than 0.5 using either age-based central venous catheter size selection criterion (14/27) or the provider bedside ultrasound femoral vein diameter measurement (18/27). CONCLUSIONS: PICU provider measurement of femoral vein diameter by bedside ultrasound is inaccurate when compared with expert reference measurement. Central venous catheter size selection based on age or PICU provider femoral vein diameter measurement can lead to a catheter-to-vein ratio greater than 0.5 and potentially increase the risk of catheter-associated venous thromboembolism. Structured bedside ultrasound training with assessment of accuracy is necessary prior to implementation of venous thromboembolism reduction efforts based on catheter-to-vein ratio recommendations.


Asunto(s)
Cateterismo Venoso Central , Vena Femoral , Cateterismo Venoso Central/efectos adversos , Niño , Vena Femoral/diagnóstico por imagen , Humanos , Lactante , Unidades de Cuidado Intensivo Pediátrico , Estudios Prospectivos , Ultrasonografía
8.
J Med Ethics ; 2020 Jul 09.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32647047

RESUMEN

Digital apps using Bluetooth to log proximity events (henceforth, digital contact tracing) are increasingly supported by technologists and governments. By and large, the public debate on this matter focuses on privacy, with experts from both law and technology offering very concrete proposals and participating to a lively debate. Far less attention is paid to effective incentives and their fairness. This paper aims to fill this gap by offering a practical, workable solution for a promising incentive, justified by the ethical principles of non-maleficence, beneficence, autonomy and justice. This incentive is a free phone optimised for running such app.

9.
J Med Ethics ; 2020 Nov 25.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33239471

RESUMEN

In his recent article 'Limits of trust in medical AI,' Hatherley argues that, if we believe that the motivations that are usually recognised as relevant for interpersonal trust have to be applied to interactions between humans and medical artificial intelligence, then these systems do not appear to be the appropriate objects of trust. In this response, we argue that it is possible to discuss trust in medical artificial intelligence (AI), if one refrains from simply assuming that trust describes human-human interactions. To do so, we consider an account of trust that distinguishes trust from reliance in a way that is compatible with trusting non-human agents. In this account, to trust a medical AI is to rely on it with little monitoring and control of the elements that make it trustworthy. This attitude does not imply specific properties in the AI system that in fact only humans can have. This account of trust is applicable, in particular, to all cases where a physician relies on the medical AI predictions to support his or her decision making.

10.
Transfusion ; 58(8): 2003-2012, 2018 08.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30171813

RESUMEN

BACKGROUND: Three methods of leukoreduction (LR) are used worldwide: filtration, buffy coat removal (BCR), and a combination of the previous two methods. Additionally, there are a number of additive solutions (ASs) used to preserve red blood cell (RBC) function throughout storage. During RBC storage, proinflammatory activity accumulates; thus, we hypothesize that both the method of LR and the AS affect the accumulation of proinflammatory activity. STUDY DESIGN AND METHODS: Ten units of whole blood were drawn from healthy donors, the RBC units were isolated, divided in half by weight, and leukoreduced by: 1) BCR, 2) filtration, or 3) BCR and filtration (combination-LR); stored in bags containing AS-3 per AABB criteria; and sampled weekly. The supernatants were isolated and frozen (-80°C). RBC units drawn from healthy donors into AS-1-, AS-3-, or AS-5-containing bags were also stored and sampled weekly, and the supernatants were isolated and frozen. The supernatants were assayed for neutrophil (PMN)-priming activity and underwent proteomic analyses. RESULTS: Filtration and combination LR decreased priming activity accumulation versus buffy coat LR, although the accumulation of priming activity was not different during storage. Combination LR increased hemolysis versus filtration via proteomic analysis. Priming activity from AS-3 units was significant later in storage versus AS-1- or AS-5-stored units. CONCLUSIONS: Although both filtration and combination LR decrease the accumulation of proinflammatory activity versus buffy coat LR, combination LR is not more advantageous over filtration, has increased costs, and may cause increased hemolysis. In addition, AS-3 decreases the early accumulation of PMN-priming activity during storage versus AS-1 or AS-5.


Asunto(s)
Conservación de la Sangre/métodos , Eritrocitos/citología , Procedimientos de Reducción del Leucocitos , Activación Neutrófila , Capa Leucocitaria de la Sangre , Filtración , Humanos , Inflamación , Métodos , Soluciones
12.
J Med Ethics ; 42(9): 574-7, 2016 09.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27009980

RESUMEN

I sketch a libertarian argument for the right to test in the context of 'direct to consumer' (DTC) genetic testing. A libertarian right to genetic tests, as defined here, relies on the idea of a moral right to self-ownership. I show how a libertarian right to test can be inferred from this general libertarian premise, at least as a prima facie right, shifting the burden of justification on regulators. I distinguish this distinctively libertarian position from some arguments based on considerations of utility or autonomy, which are sometimes labelled 'libertarian' because they oppose a tight regulation of the direct to consumer genetic testing sector. If one takes the libertarian right to test as a starting point, the whole discussion concerning autonomy and personal utility may be sidestepped. Finally, I briefly consider some considerations that justify the regulation of the DTC genetic testing market, compatible with the recognition of a prima facie right to test.


Asunto(s)
Acceso a la Información/ética , Pruebas Dirigidas al Consumidor , Libertad , Investigación Genética/ética , Pruebas Genéticas , Propiedad/ética , Acceso a la Información/legislación & jurisprudencia , Participación de la Comunidad , Formación de Concepto , Pruebas Dirigidas al Consumidor/ética , Pruebas Genéticas/ética , Humanos , Propiedad/legislación & jurisprudencia , Formulación de Políticas , Revelación de la Verdad
14.
Bioethics ; 29(8): 580-7, 2015 Oct.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25644664

RESUMEN

Recent evidence of intergenerational epigenetic programming of disease risk broadens the scope of public health preventive interventions to future generations, i.e. non existing people. Due to the transmission of epigenetic predispositions, lifestyles such as smoking or unhealthy diet might affect the health of populations across several generations. While public policy for the health of future generations can be justified through impersonal considerations, such as maximizing aggregate well-being, in this article we explore whether there are rights-based obligations supervening on intergenerational epigenetic programming despite the non-identity argument, which challenges this rationale in case of policies that affect the number and identity of future people. We propose that rights based obligations grounded in the interests of non-existing people might fall upon existing people when generations overlap. In particular, if environmental exposure in F0 (i.e. existing people) will affect the health of F2 (i.e. non-existing people) through epigenetic programming, then F1 (i.e. existing and overlapping with both F0 and F2) might face increased costs to address F2's condition in the future: this might generate obligations upon F0 from various distributive principles, such as the principle of equal opportunity for well being.


Asunto(s)
Exposición a Riesgos Ambientales , Epigénesis Genética , Interacción Gen-Ambiente , Predisposición Genética a la Enfermedad , Política de Salud , Relaciones Intergeneracionales , Estilo de Vida , Obligaciones Morales , Responsabilidad Social , Epigenómica , Conducta Alimentaria , Política de Salud/tendencias , Estado de Salud , Humanos , Autonomía Personal , Política Pública/tendencias , Fumar/efectos adversos
15.
Kennedy Inst Ethics J ; 24(4): 323-44, 2014 Dec.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25638946

RESUMEN

Many people believe that individuals have a right not to know their genetic disease risk. Here it is argued that, if this is correct, individuals also have a right not to know their diet-related disease risk. Reasons to remain ignorant are analogous in the case of risk related to diet and genetic susceptibilities. It follows that any policy to promote healthy diets (e.g. through "judgmental" food labels, such as traffic light labels, or, hypothetically, scary pictures similar to those found in cigarette packets) ought to protect the individual right not to know.


Asunto(s)
Conducta de Elección , Comportamiento del Consumidor , Conducta Alimentaria/psicología , Etiquetado de Alimentos/ética , Pruebas Genéticas , Conocimientos, Actitudes y Práctica en Salud , Autonomía Personal , Estrés Psicológico/etiología , Susceptibilidad a Enfermedades , Etiquetado de Alimentos/normas , Etiquetado de Alimentos/tendencias , Predisposición Genética a la Enfermedad , Pruebas Genéticas/ética , Política de Salud , Humanos , Juicio , Valor Nutritivo , Salud Pública , Factores de Riesgo , Discriminación Social , Valores Sociales , Estereotipo , Estrés Psicológico/prevención & control
17.
J Med Ethics ; 39(12): 748-51, 2013 Dec.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23349511

RESUMEN

Does biomedical enhancement challenge justice in health care? This paper argues that health care justice based on the concept of normal functioning is inadequate if enhancements are widespread. Two different interpretations of normal functioning are distinguished: the "species typical" vs. the "normal cooperator" account, showing that each version of the theory fails to account for certain egalitarian intuitions about help and assistance owed to people with health needs, where enhancements are widespread.


Asunto(s)
Refuerzo Biomédico/ética , Accesibilidad a los Servicios de Salud/ética , Necesidades y Demandas de Servicios de Salud , Justicia Social/ética , Atención a la Salud/clasificación , Atención a la Salud/ética , Humanos , Defensa del Paciente/ética , Asignación de Recursos
18.
J Med Ethics ; 44(11): 790, 2018 11.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-28821578
20.
Monash Bioeth Rev ; 31(2): 60-82, 2013 Sep.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24844081

RESUMEN

This paper articulates a careful and detailed objection to the moral permissibility of postnatal abortion. Giubilini and Minerva (2012) claim that if being unable to nurture one's newborn child without significant burdens to oneself, family or society, is a proper moral ground for the demand that the life of a fetus be terminated, then 'after-birth abortion should be considered a permissible option for women who would be damaged by [rearing the child or] giving up their newborns for adoption.' It will be shown that the permissibility of postnatal abortion does not follow from the argument's premises, in particular, the premise that the newborn is not a person in the morally relevant sense.


Asunto(s)
Aborto Inducido/ética , Recién Nacido/psicología , Infanticidio/ética , Bienestar Materno/ética , Principios Morales , Periodo Posparto/ética , Aborto Inducido/psicología , Adopción/psicología , Comienzo de la Vida Humana/ética , Niño Abandonado/psicología , Femenino , Humanos , Infanticidio/psicología , Bienestar Materno/psicología , Embarazo , Embarazo no Deseado/ética , Embarazo no Deseado/psicología
SELECCIÓN DE REFERENCIAS
DETALLE DE LA BÚSQUEDA