Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Mostrar: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 20 de 82
Filtrar
Más filtros

Banco de datos
Tipo del documento
Intervalo de año de publicación
1.
Am J Bioeth ; 23(1): 12-24, 2023 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36219208

RESUMEN

While experience often affords important knowledge and insight that is difficult to garner through observation or testimony alone, it also has the potential to generate conflicts of interest and unrepresentative perspectives. We call this tension the paradox of experience. In this paper, we first outline appeals to experience made in debates about access to unproven medical products and disability bioethics, as examples of how experience claims arise in bioethics and some of the challenges raised by these claims. We then motivate the idea that experience can be an asset by appealing to themes in feminist and moral epistemology, distinguishing between epistemic and justice-based appeals. Next, we explain the concern that experience may be a liability by appealing to empirical work on cognitive biases and theoretical work about the problem of partial representation. We conclude with preliminary recommendations for addressing the paradox and offer several questions for future discussion.


Asunto(s)
Bioética , Humanos , Principios Morales , Feminismo , Justicia Social
2.
Clin Trials ; 18(2): 226-233, 2021 04.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33530721

RESUMEN

Given the dearth of established safe and effective interventions to respond to COVID-19, there is an urgent ethical imperative to conduct meaningful clinical research. The good news is that interventions to be tested are not in short supply. Unfortunately, the human and material resources needed to conduct these trials are finite. It is essential that trials be robust and meet enrollment targets and that lower-quality studies not be permitted to displace higher-quality studies, delaying answers to critical questions. Yet, with few exceptions, existing research review bodies and processes are not designed to ensure these conditions are satisfied. To meet this challenge, we offer guidance for research institutions about how to ethically consolidate and prioritize COVID-19 clinical trials, while recognizing that consolidation and prioritization should also take place upstream (among manufacturers and funders) and at a higher level (e.g. nationally). In our proposed three-stage process, trials must first meet threshold criteria. Those that do are evaluated in a second stage to determine whether the institution has sufficient capacity to support all proposed trials. If it does not, the third stage entails evaluating studies against two additional sets of comparative prioritization criteria: those specific to the study and those that aim to advance diversification of an institution's research portfolio. To implement these criteria fairly, we propose that research institutions form COVID-19 research prioritization committees. We briefly discuss some important attributes of these committees, drawing on the authors' experiences at our respective institutions. Although we focus on clinical trials of COVID-19 therapeutics, our guidance should prove useful for other kinds of COVID-19 research, as well as non-pandemic research, which can raise similar challenges due to the scarcity of research resources.


Asunto(s)
COVID-19/terapia , Ensayos Clínicos como Asunto/ética , Ensayos Clínicos como Asunto/organización & administración , Investigación Biomédica/ética , Investigación Biomédica/organización & administración , Comités de Ética en Investigación , Ética en Investigación , Prioridades en Salud , Recursos en Salud , Humanos , Proyectos de Investigación , SARS-CoV-2
3.
Am J Bioeth ; 21(12): 4-19, 2021 12.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34665689

RESUMEN

After witnessing extraordinary scientific and regulatory efforts to speed development of and access to new COVID-19 interventions, patients facing other serious diseases have begun to ask "where's our Operation Warp Speed?" and "why isn't Emergency Use Authorization an option for our health crises?" Although this pandemic bears a number of unique features, the response to COVID-19 offers translatable lessons, in both its successes and failures, for non-pandemic diseases. These include the importance of collaborating across sectors, supporting the highest-priority research efforts, adopting rigorous and innovative trial designs, and sharing reliable information quickly. In addition, the regulatory response to the pandemic demonstrates that lowering standards for marketing authorization can result in increased safety concerns, missed opportunities for research and treatment, and delays in determining what works. Accordingly, policymakers and patient advocates seeking to build on the COVID-19 experience for non-pandemic diseases with unmet treatment needs should focus their efforts on promoting robust and efficient research designs, improving access to clinical trials, and facilitating use of the Food and Drug Administration's existing Expanded Access pathway.


Asunto(s)
COVID-19 , Pandemias , Desarrollo de Medicamentos , Humanos , SARS-CoV-2
4.
Am J Bioeth ; 21(3): 11-31, 2021 03.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33541252

RESUMEN

To prepare for potential human infection challenge studies (HICS) involving SARS-CoV-2, we convened a multidisciplinary working group to address ethical questions regarding whether and how much SARS-CoV-2 HICS participants should be paid. Because the goals of paying HICS participants, as well as the relevant ethical concerns, are the same as those arising for other types of clinical research, the same basic framework for ethical payment can apply. This framework divides payment into reimbursement, compensation, and incentives, focusing on fairness and promoting adequate recruitment and retention as counterweights to concerns about undue inducement. Within the basic framework, several factors are especially salient for HICS, and for SARS-CoV-2 HICS in particular, including the nature of participant confinement, anticipated discomfort, risks and uncertainty, participant motivations, and trust. These factors are reflected in a payment worksheet created to help sponsors, researchers, and ethics reviewers systematically develop and assess ethically justifiable payment amounts.


Asunto(s)
COVID-19 , Ética en Investigación , Humanos , Motivación , Proyectos de Investigación , SARS-CoV-2
5.
Ann Intern Med ; 173(7): 558-562, 2020 10 06.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32687743

RESUMEN

Evaluating the quality and effectiveness of the institutional review boards (IRBs) responsible for overseeing research involving human participants is critically important but perpetually challenging. Seemingly common-sense measures, such as the number of proposals approved with and without major modifications and the number of unexpected adverse events occurring in approved protocols, can be misleading indicators of participant protection, and regulatory compliance may not correspond to achieving ethical goals. These measurement challenges make it difficult to assess the validity of concerns about different IRB models. A group of U.S. senators recently raised questions about the increasing use of for-profit IRBs to review research proposals (as opposed to boards typically housed at academic medical centers and health care institutions) and, more specifically, about the growing trend of private equity ownership and consolidation of for-profit IRBs. Although all IRBs face pressure to speed reviews and none are entirely free of conflicts of interest, the private equity model is particularly susceptible to approaches that could undercut the ethical mission of IRBs to protect and promote the rights and welfare of research participants. Ideally, the quality of board oversight could be measured directly, rather than relying on the heuristic of board type; this article describes several current efforts toward this goal. In the meantime, one improvement may be to pursue a new model of IRB oversight: independent nonprofit boards that stand apart from research institutions, take advantage of business approaches to research review, and minimize conflicts of interest.


Asunto(s)
Experimentación Humana , Sector Privado/ética , Conflicto de Intereses , Comités de Ética en Investigación/legislación & jurisprudencia , Comités de Ética en Investigación/normas , Regulación Gubernamental , Experimentación Humana/legislación & jurisprudencia , Experimentación Humana/normas , Humanos , Sector Privado/organización & administración , Estados Unidos
6.
J Infect Dis ; 222(3): 356-361, 2020 07 06.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32469074

RESUMEN

Trials are in development and underway to examine potential interventions for treatment and prophylaxis of coronavirus disease 2019 (COVID-19). How should we think about offering payment to participants in these trials? Payment for research participation is ethically contentious even under ideal circumstances. Here, we review 3 functions of research payment-reimbursement, compensation, and incentive-and identify heightened and novel ethical concerns in the context of a global pandemic. We argue that COVID-19 trial participants should usually be offered reimbursement for research-related expenses, and compensation for their time and effort, as for other types of research under usual circumstances. Given increased risk of undue influence against pandemic background conditions, incentive payment should be avoided unless essential to recruitment and retention in important trials whose social value outweighs this risk. Where essential, however, incentives can be ethically permissible, so long as reasonable efforts are made to minimize the possibility of undue influence.


Asunto(s)
Ensayos Clínicos como Asunto/economía , Infecciones por Coronavirus/terapia , Voluntarios Sanos , Neumonía Viral/terapia , COVID-19 , Ensayos Clínicos como Asunto/ética , Compensación y Reparación/ética , Infecciones por Coronavirus/prevención & control , Humanos , Motivación/ética , Pandemias/prevención & control , Neumonía Viral/prevención & control , Investigación/economía
8.
Ann Intern Med ; 169(8): 559-563, 2018 10 16.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30264127

RESUMEN

A key aim of patient-centered outcomes research (PCOR) is to generate data that are important to patients by deliberately and extensively involving them in all aspects of research, from design to dissemination. However, certain elements of PCOR raise challenging and potentially novel ethical and regulatory issues for institutional review boards and oversight bodies. These challenges stem primarily from the engagement of patients in roles other than research subject, such as advisors, study personnel, and co-investigators, which gives rise to questions about appropriate levels of protection, training, and education, as well as identifying and managing conflicts of interest. This article presents and discusses recommendations from a Delphi expert panel that was convened to address these and other PCOR-related oversight challenges.


Asunto(s)
Comités de Ética en Investigación , Evaluación del Resultado de la Atención al Paciente , Técnica Delphi , Comités de Ética en Investigación/organización & administración , Humanos , Invenciones , Defensa del Paciente , Pacientes
9.
JAMA ; 2024 Jun 18.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38889181

RESUMEN

In this Viewpoint, the authors refute recent suggestions that the US Food and Drug Administration (FDA) is not accountable for its decisions, pointing out the legal, legislative, and executive checks and balances on the agency.

11.
J Med Ethics ; 43(12): 803-809, 2017 12.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-28108613

RESUMEN

It is not uncommon for multiple clinical trials at the same institution to recruit concurrently from the same patient population. When the relevant pool of patients is limited, as it often is, trials essentially compete for participants. There is evidence that such a competition is a predictor of low study accrual, with increased competition tied to increased recruitment shortfalls. But there is no consensus on what steps, if any, institutions should take to approach this issue. In this article, we argue that an institutional policy that prioritises some trials for recruitment ahead of others is ethically permissible and indeed prima facie preferable to alternative means of addressing recruitment competition. We motivate this view by appeal to the ethical importance of minimising the number of studies that begin but do not complete, thereby exposing their participants to unnecessary risks and burdens in the process. We then argue that a policy of prioritisation can be fair to relevant stakeholders, including participants, investigators and funders. Finally, by way of encouraging and helping to frame future debate, we propose some questions that would need to be addressed when identifying substantive ethical criteria for prioritising between studies.


Asunto(s)
Investigación Biomédica/ética , Toma de Decisiones/ética , Prioridades en Salud/ética , Política Organizacional , Selección de Paciente/ética , Humanos
12.
Am J Bioeth ; 17(3): 3-14, 2017 Mar.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-28207365

RESUMEN

The use of social media as a recruitment tool for research with humans is increasing, and likely to continue to grow. Despite this, to date there has been no specific regulatory guidance and there has been little in the bioethics literature to guide investigators and institutional review boards (IRBs) faced with navigating the ethical issues such use raises. We begin to fill this gap by first defending a nonexceptionalist methodology for assessing social media recruitment; second, examining respect for privacy and investigator transparency as key norms governing social media recruitment; and, finally, analyzing three relatively novel aspects of social media recruitment: (i) the ethical significance of compliance with website "terms of use"; (ii) the ethics of recruiting from the online networks of research participants; and (iii) the ethical implications of online communication from and between participants. Two checklists aimed at guiding investigators and IRBs through the ethical issues are included as appendices.


Asunto(s)
Investigación Biomédica/ética , Selección de Paciente/ética , Medios de Comunicación Sociales/ética , Confidencialidad/ética , Ética en Investigación , Humanos , Consentimiento Informado , Relaciones Médico-Paciente/ética
15.
J Med Ethics ; 42(4): 229-34, 2016 Apr.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-26811365

RESUMEN

A novel Protocol Ethics Tool Kit ('Ethics Tool Kit') has been developed by a multi-stakeholder group of the Multi-Regional Clinical Trials Center of Brigham and Women's Hospital and Harvard. The purpose of the Ethics Tool Kit is to facilitate effective recognition, consideration and deliberation of critical ethical issues in clinical trial protocols. The Ethics Tool Kit may be used by investigators and sponsors to develop a dedicated Ethics Section within a protocol to improve the consistency and transparency between clinical trial protocols and research ethics committee reviews. It may also streamline ethics review and may facilitate and expedite the review process by anticipating the concerns of ethics committee reviewers. Specific attention was given to issues arising in multinational settings. With the use of this Tool Kit, researchers have the opportunity to address critical research ethics issues proactively, potentially speeding the time and easing the process to final protocol approval.


Asunto(s)
Investigación Biomédica/ética , Protocolos Clínicos/normas , Ensayos Clínicos como Asunto/ética , Comités de Ética en Investigación , Ética en Investigación , Proyectos de Investigación/normas , Revisión Ética , Ética en Investigación/educación , Humanos , Obligaciones Morales , Investigadores/ética
19.
Yale J Health Policy Law Ethics ; 14(1): 122-93, 2014.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25051653

RESUMEN

Biomedical research involving human subjects has traditionally been treated as a unique endeavor, presenting special risks and demanding special protections. But in several ways, the regulatory scheme governing human subjects research is counter-intuitively less protective than the labor and employment laws applicable to many workers. This Article relies on analogical and legal reasoning to demonstrate that this should not be the case; in a number of ways, human research subjects ought to be fundamentally recast as human research workers. Like other workers protected under worklaw, biomedical research subjects often have interests that diverge from those in positions of control but little bargaining power for change. Bearing these important similarities in mind, the question becomes whether there is any good reason to treat subjects and protected workers differently as a matter of law. With regard to unrestricted payment, eligibility for a minimum wage, compensation for injury, and rights to engage in concerted activity, the answer is no and human subjects regulations ought to be revised accordingly.


Asunto(s)
Empleo/economía , Empleo/ética , Renta , Sujetos de Investigación/economía , Sujetos de Investigación/legislación & jurisprudencia , Investigación Biomédica/ética , Negociación Colectiva/ética , Negociación Colectiva/legislación & jurisprudencia , Compensación y Reparación/ética , Compensación y Reparación/legislación & jurisprudencia , Empleo/legislación & jurisprudencia , Humanos , Sindicatos , Desempleo , Estados Unidos
SELECCIÓN DE REFERENCIAS
DETALLE DE LA BÚSQUEDA