Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Mostrar: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 20 de 42
Filtrar
Mais filtros

Base de dados
Tipo de documento
País de afiliação
Intervalo de ano de publicação
1.
Am J Respir Crit Care Med ; 201(10): 1182-1192, 2020 05 15.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32412853

RESUMO

Background and Rationale: ICU clinicians regularly care for patients who lack capacity, an applicable advance directive, and an available surrogate decision-maker. Although there is no consensus on terminology, we refer to these patients as "unrepresented." There is considerable controversy about how to make treatment decisions for these patients, and there is significant variability in both law and clinical practice.Purpose and Objectives: This multisociety statement provides clinicians and hospital administrators with recommendations for decision-making on behalf of unrepresented patients in the critical care setting.Methods: An interprofessional, multidisciplinary expert committee developed this policy statement by using an iterative consensus process with a diverse working group representing critical care medicine, palliative care, pediatric medicine, nursing, social work, gerontology, geriatrics, patient advocacy, bioethics, philosophy, elder law, and health law.Main Results: The committee designed its policy recommendations to promote five ethical goals: 1) to protect highly vulnerable patients, 2) to demonstrate respect for persons, 3) to provide appropriate medical care, 4) to safeguard against unacceptable discrimination, and 5) to avoid undue influence of competing obligations and conflicting interests. These recommendations also are intended to strike an appropriate balance between excessive and insufficient procedural safeguards. The committee makes the following recommendations: 1) institutions should offer advance care planning to prevent patients at high risk for becoming unrepresented from meeting this definition; 2) institutions should implement strategies to determine whether seemingly unrepresented patients are actually unrepresented, including careful capacity assessments and diligent searches for potential surrogates; 3) institutions should manage decision-making for unrepresented patients using input from a diverse interprofessional, multidisciplinary committee rather than ad hoc by treating clinicians; 4) institutions should use all available information on the patient's preferences and values to guide treatment decisions; 5) institutions should manage decision-making for unrepresented patients using a fair process that comports with procedural due process; 6) institutions should employ this fair process even when state law authorizes procedures with less oversight.Conclusions: This multisociety statement provides guidance for clinicians and hospital administrators on medical decision-making for unrepresented patients in the critical care setting.


Assuntos
Cuidados Críticos/normas , Tomada de Decisões/ética , Unidades de Terapia Intensiva , Procurador , Planejamento Antecipado de Cuidados , Tomada de Decisão Clínica , Cuidados Críticos/ética , Geriatria , Humanos , Julgamento , Defesa do Paciente , Equipe de Assistência ao Paciente , Preferência do Paciente , Pneumologia , Sociedades Médicas
2.
HEC Forum ; 33(3): 307-324, 2021 Sep.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34415464

RESUMO

This special issue of HEC Forum includes articles on a wide range of specific topics that make significant contributions to conscientious objection scholarship. In this commentary, it is not feasible to provide a comprehensive analysis of each of the articles; and I have not attempted to do so. Instead, for each article, I have selected specific issues and arguments on which to comment.


Assuntos
Consciência , Dissidências e Disputas , Editoração/tendências , Humanos , Editoração/normas
3.
Perspect Biol Med ; 62(3): 543-559, 2019.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31495797

RESUMO

Lauris Kaldjian defends conscientious objection against opponents who claim that there is no place for a physician's personal moral beliefs in the practice of medicine. This essay argues that Kaldjian's defense of conscientious objection relies on a controversial "thick" conception of conscience that opponents may justifiably question. It offers a defense that relies on a relatively "thin" conception of conscience as an agent's core moral beliefs and that understands conscience-based refusals to provide medical services as refusals based on those core beliefs. Enabling physicians to practice medicine without compromising their moral integrity is an important pro tanto reason to accommodate physicians who conscientiously object to providing medical services. However, giving due consideration to the professional obligations of physicians requires constraints on accommodation. Accommodation should not: (1) impede a patient's timely access to relevant information; (2) impede a patient's timely access to referral and counselling; (3) impede a patient's timely access to medical services that are consistent with prevailing professional standards; (4) enable physicians to practice invidious discrimination; (5) place an excessive burden on other health professionals and institutions; or (6) authorize physicians to unilaterally decide to forgo life-sustaining treatment against the wishes of patients or surrogates.


Assuntos
Princípios Morais , Relações Médico-Paciente/ética , Médicos/ética , Atitude do Pessoal de Saúde , Consciência , Recusa Consciente em Tratar-se/ética , Dissidências e Disputas , Humanos , Obrigações Morais , Sociedades Médicas , Suicídio Assistido/ética , Suicídio Assistido/legislação & jurisprudência , Estados Unidos
4.
Camb Q Healthc Ethics ; 27(3): 497-510, 2018 07.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-29845923

RESUMO

Humans is a science fiction television series set in what appears to be present-day London. What makes it science fiction is that in London and worldwide, there are robots that look like humans and can mimic human behavior. The series raises several important ethical and philosophical questions about artificial intelligence and robotics, which should be of interest to bioethicists.


Assuntos
Robótica , Televisão , Inteligência Artificial , Robótica/ética , Reino Unido , Estados Unidos
5.
Camb Q Healthc Ethics ; 26(1): 7-17, 2017 Jan.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27934564

RESUMO

There are several reasons for accommodating health professionals' conscientious objections. However, several authors have argued that among the most important and compelling reasons is to enable health professionals to maintain their moral integrity. Accommodation is said to provide "moral space" in which health professionals can practice without compromising their moral integrity. There are, however, alternative conceptions of moral integrity and corresponding different criteria for moral-integrity-based claims. It is argued that one conception of moral integrity, the identity conception, is sound and suitable in the specific context of responding to health professionals' conscientious objections and their requests for accommodation. According to the identity conception, one maintains one's moral integrity if and only if one's actions are consistent with one's core moral convictions. The identity conception has been subject to a number of criticisms that might call into question its suitability as a standard for determining whether health professionals have genuine moral-integrity-based accommodation claims. The following five objections to the identity conception are critically examined: (1) it does not include a social component, (2) it is a conception of subjective rather than objective integrity, (3) it does not include a reasonableness condition, (4) it does not include any substantive moral constraints, and (5) it does not include any intellectual integrity requirement. In response to these objections, it is argued that none establishes the unsuitability of the identity conception in the specific context of responding to health professionals' conscientious objections and their requests for accommodation.


Assuntos
Consciência , Atenção à Saúde/ética , Pessoal de Saúde/ética , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Humanos , Princípios Morais
6.
Am J Respir Crit Care Med ; 191(2): 219-27, 2015 Jan 15.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25590155

RESUMO

RATIONALE: Intensive care unit (ICU) clinicians sometimes have a conscientious objection (CO) to providing or disclosing information about a legal, professionally accepted, and otherwise available medical service. There is little guidance about how to manage COs in ICUs. OBJECTIVES: To provide clinicians, hospital administrators, and policymakers with recommendations for managing COs in the critical care setting. METHODS: This policy statement was developed by a multidisciplinary expert committee using an iterative process with a diverse working group representing adult medicine, pediatrics, nursing, patient advocacy, bioethics, philosophy, and law. MAIN RESULTS: The policy recommendations are based on the dual goals of protecting patients' access to medical services and protecting the moral integrity of clinicians. Conceptually, accommodating COs should be considered a "shield" to protect individual clinicians' moral integrity rather than as a "sword" to impose clinicians' judgments on patients. The committee recommends that: (1) COs in ICUs be managed through institutional mechanisms, (2) institutions accommodate COs, provided doing so will not impede a patient's or surrogate's timely access to medical services or information or create excessive hardships for other clinicians or the institution, (3) a clinician's CO to providing potentially inappropriate or futile medical services should not be considered sufficient justification to forgo the treatment against the objections of the patient or surrogate, and (4) institutions promote open moral dialogue and foster a culture that respects diverse values in the critical care setting. CONCLUSIONS: This American Thoracic Society statement provides guidance for clinicians, hospital administrators, and policymakers to address clinicians' COs in the critical care setting.


Assuntos
Acesso à Informação/ética , Consciência , Acessibilidade aos Serviços de Saúde/ética , Unidades de Terapia Intensiva/ética , Direitos do Paciente/ética , Autonomia Profissional , Acesso à Informação/legislação & jurisprudência , Adolescente , Adulto , Idoso , Atitude do Pessoal de Saúde , Temas Bioéticos , Criança , Revelação/ética , Revelação/legislação & jurisprudência , Feminino , Guias como Assunto , Acessibilidade aos Serviços de Saúde/legislação & jurisprudência , Humanos , Lactente , Unidades de Terapia Intensiva/legislação & jurisprudência , Masculino , Pessoa de Meia-Idade , Política Organizacional , Direitos do Paciente/legislação & jurisprudência , Gravidez , Sociedades Médicas/ética , Estados Unidos , Recursos Humanos
7.
Am J Bioeth ; 21(8): 65-67, 2021 Aug.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34313572
9.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 44(5): 33-42, 2014 09.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25231660

RESUMO

Physicians are expected to engage patients as partners in identifying the possible benefits and harms associated with treatment options and selecting from among medically appropriate treatment options, rather than simply dictating what treatments patients will and will not receive. This collaborative model reflects the recognition that citizens in multicultural societies have diverse values and are likely to have different views about whether the possible benefits of a medical intervention outweigh the possible harms. However, there are circumstances in which the collaborative process breaks down due to irresolvable disagreement. Especially challenging are cases in which patients are expected to die if they do not receive a treatment and either the patients or their surrogates insist on the treatment despite the physician's belief that providing it is ill advised. The source of disagreement is often differing appraisals of the risks and potential benefits. In such cases, physicians generally judge that there is insufficient likelihood or magnitude of benefit to justify the burdens or expense of treatment, while patients or surrogates believe that the small chance of preventing the patient's death is sufficient to justify the costs and potential burdens to the patient. There is a perception that surgeons enjoy considerable discretion in deciding when the risks of a procedure outweigh the expected benefits. An important contrast can be drawn between surgeons and intensivists-physicians who specialize in the medical management of critically ill patients. We will argue that there are good reasons for subjecting the decisions of both surgeons and intensivists to some oversight. We begin by showing that, for many cases, major professional society guidelines for intensivists recommend oversight via a procedural mechanism rather than unilateral decision-making by individual clinicians. Next, we present reasons for adopting a procedural approach to dispute resolution, and we argue that these reasons apply to situations in which intensivists believe that patients or surrogates are requesting inappropriate life support as well as to many disagreements between surgeons and surrogates. Finally, we present and respond to several objections.


Assuntos
Temas Bioéticos , Dissidências e Disputas , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Cirurgiões/ética , Tomada de Decisão Clínica , Humanos , Princípios Morais , Participação do Paciente , Médicos/ética , Guias de Prática Clínica como Assunto
10.
HEC Forum ; 26(3): 267-83, 2014 Sep.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24975827

RESUMO

It is argued that the primary aim of institutional management is to protect the moral integrity of health professionals without significantly compromising other important values and interests. Institutional policies are recommended as a means to promote fair, consistent, and transparent management of conscience-based refusals. It is further recommended that those policies include the following four requirements: (1) Conscience-based refusals will be accommodated only if a requested accommodation will not impede a patient's/surrogate's timely access to information, counseling, and referral. (2) Conscience-based refusals will be accommodated only if a requested accommodation will not impede a patient's timely access to health care services offered within the institution. (3) Conscience-based refusals will be accommodated only if the accommodation will not impose excessive burdens on colleagues, supervisors, department heads, other administrators, or the institution. (4) Whenever feasible, health professionals should provide advance notification to department heads or supervisors. Formal review may not be required in all cases, but when it is appropriate, several recommendations are offered about standards and the review process. A key recommendation is that when reviewing an objector's reasons, contrary to what some have proposed, it is not appropriate to adopt an adversarial approach modelled on military review boards' assessments of requests for conscientious objector status. According to the approach recommended, the primary function of reviews of objectors' reasons is to engage them in a process of reflecting on the nature and depth of their objections, with the objective of facilitating moral clarity on the part of objectors rather than enabling department heads, supervisors, or ethics committees to determine whether conscientious objections are sufficiently genuine.


Assuntos
Dissidências e Disputas , Pessoal de Saúde/ética , Política Organizacional , Religião , Consciência , Humanos , Encaminhamento e Consulta/ética
12.
Nat Med ; 11(11): 1145-9, 2005 Nov.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-16270065

RESUMO

The objective of the multidisciplinary expert Consensus Panel on Research with the Recently Dead (CPRRD) was to craft ethics guidelines for research with the recently dead. The CPRRD recommends that research with the recently dead: (i) receive scientific and ethical review and oversight; (ii) involve the community of potential research subjects; (iii) be coordinated with organ procurement organizations; (iv) not conflict with organ donation or required autopsy; (v) use procedures respectful of the dead; (vi) be restricted to one procedure per day; (vii) preferably be authorized by first-person consent, though both general advance research directives and surrogate consent are acceptable; (viii) protect confidentiality; (ix) not impose costs on subjects' estates or next of kin and not involve payment; (x) clearly explain ultimate disposition of the body.


Assuntos
Morte , Revisão Ética , Comitês de Ética em Pesquisa , Guias como Assunto , Pesquisa , Humanos , Estados Unidos
14.
Theor Med Bioeth ; 40(6): 539-564, 2019 Dec.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31797214

RESUMO

A US Department of Health and Human Services Final Rule, Protecting Statutory Conscience Rights in Health Care (2019), and a proposed bill in the British House of Lords, the Conscientious Objection (Medical Activities) Bill (2017), may well warrant a concern that-to borrow a phrase Daniel Callahan applied to self-determination-conscientious objection in health care has "run amok." Insofar as there are no significant constraints or limitations on accommodation, both rules endorse an approach that is aptly designated "conscience absolutism." There are two common strategies to counter conscience absolutism and prevent conscientious objection in medicine from running amok. One, non-toleration, is to decline to accommodate physicians who refuse to provide legal, professionally accepted, clinically appropriate medical services within the scope of their clinical competence. The other, compromise or reasonable accommodation, is to impose constraints on accommodation. Several arguments for non-toleration are critically analyzed, and I argue that none warrants its acceptance. I maintain that non-toleration is an excessively blunt instrument to prevent conscientious objection in medicine from running amok. Instead, I defend a more nuanced contextual approach that includes constraints on accommodation.


Assuntos
Consciência , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Atitude do Pessoal de Saúde , Humanos , Obrigações Morais , Assistência Centrada no Paciente/ética , Assistência Centrada no Paciente/legislação & jurisprudência , Médicos/ética , Médicos/psicologia , Recusa em Tratar/legislação & jurisprudência
16.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 48(5): 22-25, 2018 09.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30311195

RESUMO

In "Disentangling Conscience Protections," in this issue of the Hastings Center Report, Nadia Sawicki offers a taxonomy of conscience protection laws (conscience clauses) that highlights the expansive protections they can offer to health professionals who refuse to provide a medical service for reasons of conscience. Conscience clauses can protect health professionals from adverse actions by public actors (such as administrative agencies, prosecutors, and government funders) or private actors (such as employers, private professional associations, and injured patients), and they can also protect health professionals from being subject to adverse actions for their beliefs, their conduct, or harm that results from their conduct. This taxonomy provides an accurate description of the broad range of protections conscience clauses can offer and thereby is a valuable contribution to the scholarly literature on conscientious objection in health care. But it remains to consider whether the distinctions Sawicki identifies disentangle conscience protections beyond merely providing a taxonomy. In particular, does the taxonomy identify relevant distinctions in relation to determining whether a conscience clause is justified?


Assuntos
Consciência , Recusa em Tratar , Atenção à Saúde , Pessoal de Saúde , Humanos
19.
Kennedy Inst Ethics J ; 16(3): 225-50, 2006 Sep.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-17091559

RESUMO

This paper examines the obligations of pharmacy licensees and pharmacists in the context of conscience-based objections to filling lawful prescriptions for certain types of medications--e.g., standard and emergency contraceptives. Claims of conscience are analyzed as means to preserve or maintain an individual's moral integrity. It is argued that pharmacy licensees have an obligation to dispense prescription medications that satisfy the health needs of the populations they serve, and this obligation can override claims of conscience. Although efforts should be made to respect the moral integrity of pharmacists and accommodate their claims of conscience, it is argued that the health needs of patients and the professional obligations of pharmacists limit the extent to which pharmacists may refuse to assist patients who have lawful prescriptions for medically indicated drugs.


Assuntos
Consciência , Anticoncepcionais Pós-Coito , Farmácias/ética , Farmacêuticos/ética , Recusa em Tratar/ética , Códigos de Ética , Anticoncepcionais Pós-Coito/provisão & distribuição , Prescrições de Medicamentos , Emprego/ética , Ética Profissional , Feminino , Humanos , Farmácias/legislação & jurisprudência , Responsabilidade Social , Estados Unidos
SELEÇÃO DE REFERÊNCIAS
DETALHE DA PESQUISA