Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Mostrar: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 20 de 5.334
Filtrar
Más filtros

Intervalo de año de publicación
1.
Bioethics ; 38(8): 722-727, 2024 Oct.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38923008

RESUMEN

This article starts by examining the present state of death ethics by attending to the euthanasia debate. Given that voluntary active euthanasia has seen strong support in the academic community, insights on the choiceworthiness of continued existence may be derived. Having derived cases of choiceworthy nonexistence (which I refer to as choiceworthy nonexistence [CNE] cases), I extend these intuitions to lives not worth starting, or choiceworthy nonexistence for potential people (which I refer to as foetal-CNE, or fCNE cases). Although I depart from Benatarian antinatalism by rejecting Benatar's claim that all existence is necessarily a harm, I posit a weaker argument that all existence is likely a harm since we cannot know until later in life if an existence is a harm. If I am right, then we have prudential reasons not to bear children, since they are more likely to suffer in lives not worth living than not.


Asunto(s)
Eutanasia , Humanos , Eutanasia/ética , Valor de la Vida , Conducta de Elección/ética , Comienzo de la Vida Humana/ética , Disentimientos y Disputas , Análisis Ético , Derecho a Morir/ética
2.
Bioethics ; 38(4): 292-299, 2024 May.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38165658

RESUMEN

Consensual homicide remains a crime in jurisdictions where active voluntary euthanasia has been legalized. At the same time, both jurisdictions, in which euthanasia is legal and those in which it is not, recognize that all patients (whether severely ill or not) have the right to refuse or withdraw medical treatment (including life-saving treatment). In this paper, I focus on the tensions between these three norms (the permission of active euthanasia, the permission to reject life-saving treatment, and the prohibition of consensual homicide), assuming a justification of euthanasia based on the right to (personal) autonomy. I argue that the best way to provide a coherent account of these norms is to claim that patients have two distinct rights: the right to autonomy and the right to bodily integrity. This solution has some relevant implications for the discussion of the legalization of active euthanasia.


Asunto(s)
Eutanasia , Suicidio Asistido , Humanos , Homicidio , Derecho a Morir , Libertad , Autonomía Personal , Negativa del Paciente al Tratamiento , Eutanasia Activa , Eutanasia Activa Voluntaria , Eutanasia Pasiva
3.
BMC Med Ethics ; 25(1): 96, 2024 Sep 12.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-39267021

RESUMEN

BACKGROUND: Dignity is omnipresent in Western ethics, but it also provokes dissension and controversy. One of the most striking examples is the debate on medically assisted death, where dignity is invoked to support antagonistic positions. While some authors conclude that the concept is useless as an ethical reference, many others invite us to deepen our analysis from a multidimensional perspective, to enrich it and make it useful. This scoping study is intended to provide an overview of the different conceptions of dignity used in the assisted dying debate, to better grasp the multiple facets of the concept. METHODS: The Joanna Briggs Institute's JBI Manual for Evidence Synthesis guided the scoping review. Key words were based on the researchers' expertise and were used to identify relevant literature in French and English. Eleven databases covering the last six decades were consulted. Initially, 2,071 references were found in the databases. After excluding duplicates, screening titles, abstracts, and full texts, and after a specific literature search on the concept of relational dignity, 156 papers were found to match the identified inclusion criteria. RESULTS: The literature highlights the stark confrontation between two dominant conceptions of dignity: ontological and autonomist. However, a lesser-known conceptualization of dignity integrates these two perspectives, underlining the relational and social dimensions of dignity. As a result, dignity emerges as a dynamic, experiential, and dialogical concept, that modulates itself according to circumstances. This raises the possibility of breaking through the binary debate and questioning the current frameworks that define dignity. CONCLUSIONS: This multidimensional conceptualization of dignity could lead to a more complete and nuanced understanding of the concept, as well as open richer normative horizons regarding the issue of medically assisted death.


Asunto(s)
Derecho a Morir , Suicidio Asistido , Humanos , Suicidio Asistido/ética , Derecho a Morir/ética , Personeidad , Respeto
4.
Med Health Care Philos ; 27(2): 181-188, 2024 Jun.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38376767

RESUMEN

Even in the Netherlands, where the practice of physician-assisted death (PAD) has been legalized for over 20 years, there is no such thing as a 'right to die'. Especially patients with extraordinary requests, such as a wish for PAD based on psychiatric suffering, advanced dementia, or (a limited number of) multiple geriatric syndromes, encounter barriers in access to PAD. In this paper, we discuss whether these barriers can be justified in the context of the Dutch situation where PAD is legally permitted for those who suffer unbearably and hopelessly as a result of medical conditions. Furthermore, we explore whether there are options to address some of the barriers or their consequences, both within the Dutch legal framework or by adjusting the legal framework, and whether these options are feasible. We conclude that although there are insufficient arguments to overrule the doctor's freedom of conscience in the Netherlands, there are ways to address some of the barriers, mainly by offering support to doctors that would be willing to support a request. Moreover, we believe it is morally required to reduce or mitigate where possible the negative consequences of the barriers for patients, such as the long waiting time for those who suffer from psychiatric disorders, because it is unlikely the adjustments suggested to the system will ensure reasonable access for these patient groups.


Asunto(s)
Demencia , Trastornos Mentales , Suicidio Asistido , Humanos , Países Bajos , Suicidio Asistido/ética , Suicidio Asistido/legislación & jurisprudencia , Trastornos Mentales/terapia , Derecho a Morir/ética , Derecho a Morir/legislación & jurisprudencia , Accesibilidad a los Servicios de Salud/ética
5.
Ann Fam Med ; 21(4): 370-371, 2023.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37487728

RESUMEN

Family medicine physicians take care of patients and their families "from womb to tomb." This phrase is particularly apt in Oregon, where the Death with Dignity Act allows for terminally ill patients to end their lives with self-administered medications prescribed by a physician. This story chronicles my first experience caring for a patient under the Death with Dignity Act; that night of her death at home, surrounded by the warmth of her life and loved ones, opened my mind to the possibilities of what the patient-physician relationship entails, from the routine of meeting her family to the intimacy of assisting in her decision to die.


Asunto(s)
Médicos Generales , Suicidio Asistido , Femenino , Humanos , Derecho a Morir , Relaciones Médico-Paciente , Oregon
6.
J Med Ethics ; 48(6): 358-361, 2022 06.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33883234

RESUMEN

Substituted judgment has increasingly become the accepted standard for rendering decisions for incapacitated adults in the USA. A broad exception exists with regard to patients with diminished capacity secondary to depressive disorders, as such patients' previous wishes are generally not honoured when seeking to turn down life-preserving care or pursue aid-in-dying. The result is that physicians often force involuntary treatment on patients with poor medical prognoses and/or low quality of life (PMP/LQL) as a result of their depressive symptoms when similarly situated incapacitated patients without such depressive symptoms would have their previous wishes honoured via substituted judgment. This commentary argues for reconsidering this approach and for using a substituted judgment standard for a subset of EMP/LQL patients seeking death.


Asunto(s)
Juicio , Trastornos Mentales , Adulto , Toma de Decisiones , Humanos , Trastornos Mentales/terapia , Calidad de Vida , Derecho a Morir
7.
Dev World Bioeth ; 22(2): 105-111, 2022 06.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33599371

RESUMEN

What does the Chilean Constitution say about euthanasia? When we read the Chilean Constitution we cannot find the word "euthanasia" in the text, and there is no such thing as a right to die, therefore the answer should apparently be that the Constitution does not say anything about euthanasia and, in short, euthanasia is not allowed. However, on a second reading we can find out some statements from which we can infer another answer. My aim is to show that there is room for the acceptance of euthanasia in the Chilean Constitution, and in other similar Constitutions and international regulations in which freedom of conscience is granted.


Asunto(s)
Eutanasia , Derecho a Morir , Chile , Eutanasia Pasiva , Libertad , Humanos , Autonomía Personal
8.
Artículo en Alemán | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34919151

RESUMEN

In 2020, the Federal Constitutional Court declared the ban on assisted suicide unconstitutional and invalid. The court derived a right to self-determined dying from the general right of personality. This right also includes the freedom to take one's own life and to seek help from third parties for this purpose and to make use of help if it is offered. In the meantime, there are several proposals for regulations and draft laws that pursue different concepts of a possible future regulation of assisted suicide. However, from the perspective of criminal law, the search for a new regulation should always be preceded by the question of the necessity of a new regulation. A new regulation must not be limited to certain groups of persons, such as persons with incurable, terminal illnesses, because otherwise the suicide motive would be assessed. This brings with it the particular challenge of finding a regulation that covers the different problem and need situations without assessing the suicide motive and also takes into account that the autonomy of the individual can be endangered in different ways.The article takes its starting point in the right to suicide, sheds light on different concepts, and discusses their advantages and disadvantages without explicitly highlighting individual legislative proposals. This is intended to enrich the further debate with individual aspects. At the same time, it advocates legislative restraint.


Asunto(s)
Eutanasia , Suicidio Asistido , Libertad , Alemania , Humanos , Derecho a Morir
9.
Encephale ; 48(2): 196-205, 2022 Apr.
Artículo en Francés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34906375

RESUMEN

OBJECTIVES: In the context of the present re-examination of the French bioethical laws by the National Advisory Ethics Committee ("Comité consultatif national d'éthique": CCNE), a recent survey indicated a request of the public opinion to obtain a medical aid in end of life and a so-called "assisted suicide". This led psychiatrists to re-consider their role and deontological position which usually led them to consider a request for an assistance in suicide as - a priori - a pathological demand, occurring within a suicidal crisis. The present article intends to: 1) describe the laws and practices of countries which allow medically assisted end of life help procedures; 2) clarify the definitions of "assisted suicide", "assistance to suicide" and "euthanasia"; 3) consider available epidemiological data and the roles given to doctors and, more specifically psychiatrists, in these procedures; 4) analyse the rationale behind these demands. These considerations should enable French psychiatrists to clarify their position when facing requests for a medical aid in dying. METHODS: Four European countries (Switzerland, the Netherlands, Belgium, Luxemburg) and Oregon (the first US state to introduce legislation) were considered, since they accumulated and published a large amount of experiences and data about "assisted suicide" and medical help in dying. In total, 127 articles were selected, mainly from PubMed and Cairn databases, published between 1997 and 2020. These articles deal with legal considerations, epidemiological data, ethical and sociological considerations. RESULTS: Laws and practices differ notably according to the state/country. In Belgium, the Netherlands and Luxemburg, as in Oregon, the medical help in dying has been de-criminalized, as long as certain legal criteria are met. In Switzerland, where no specific law exists in the penal code, non-governmental associations have benefited from the legal vacuum and organized the practice of "assisted suicide" for "altruistic motives". In the scientific and legal literature, the terms used to describe and define the medical help in dying upon request differ greatly. In France, the National Advisory Ethics Committee defines euthanasia ("euthanasie"), assisted suicide ("suicide assisté") and suicide assistance ("assistance au suicide"). Available epidemiological data, whatever the country considered, indicate that requests for a medical aid in dying are expressed mainly by patients aged over 60 years and suffering from cancer. Psychiatric diseases account for only 1% to 3%. Most often, systematic assessment by a psychiatrist is neither requested nor made, when the demand does not occur during a primary psychiatric illness. In the case of an existing primary psychiatric pathology, a psychiatrist assesses the case against formal legal predefined criteria. This latter practice was only recently introduced, after some feedback and after legal actions had been brought to Court. When the underlying motivations of the request are considered, it appears that, even in the absence of an evolving psychiatric condition, several psychological or psychopathological reasons prevail such as spirituality, attachment style, social isolation, despair, depression… which should greatly benefit psychiatric exploration, investigation and expertise. CONCLUSION: In some countries, the request for medically assisted help in dying has become a legal and social reality. In France, where the public debate is still open, it should be emphasized that a psychiatric assessment and interview should be systematically provided to any person requesting medical assistance to die or commit suicide. It is the commitment of psychiatrists to understand the implicit demands and unexpressed motives underlying this request which have strong links with the unique life-events and emotional experiences of the person. The psychiatrist has a unique role in the contextualization of such a request.


Asunto(s)
Eutanasia , Suicidio Asistido , Anciano , Muerte , Europa (Continente) , Humanos , Derecho a Morir
10.
J Relig Health ; 60(1): 221-231, 2021 Feb.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32418151

RESUMEN

Nurses' attitudes toward spiritual care and death are influenced by their personal belief systems and world-views. The aim of this study is to reveal the attitudes of nursing students toward spiritual orientation and principles of dying with dignity. The study was conducted with the participation of 478 nursing students. As a result of the study, it was found that the average score of the students' spiritual orientation scale was high and the average score of the assessment scale of attitudes toward the principles of dying with dignity was found to be moderate.


Asunto(s)
Actitud del Personal de Salud , Derecho a Morir , Espiritualidad , Estudiantes de Enfermería , Adulto , Femenino , Humanos , Masculino , Respeto , Estudiantes de Enfermería/psicología , Estudiantes de Enfermería/estadística & datos numéricos , Turquía , Adulto Joven
11.
J Relig Health ; 60(1): 162-177, 2021 Feb.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33128221

RESUMEN

This study was conducted to determine the relationship between nurses' ethical sensitivity levels and their attitudes toward principles about die with dignity. The study was descriptive and correlational in design. The data were obtained from 226 nurses. The results of the correlation analysis conducted to determine whether there is a relationship between the nurses' ethical sensitivity level and their attitudes toward principles about die with dignity are among the autonomy, meaning and relation showed a significant, negative and low-level relationship between. As a result of the research, it was found that there was a negatively, significant and low-level relationship between autonomy, meaning and relation and attitudes toward respectable principles of death.


Asunto(s)
Actitud del Personal de Salud , Enfermeras y Enfermeros , Derecho a Morir , Ética en Enfermería , Femenino , Humanos , Masculino , Principios Morales , Enfermeras y Enfermeros/psicología , Enfermeras y Enfermeros/estadística & datos numéricos
12.
Soins Psychiatr ; 42(334): 28-31, 2021.
Artículo en Francés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34144756

RESUMEN

current evolution of society makes it possible to debate the issue of the end of life for people suffering from pathologies in which the vital prognosis is not involved; this concerns psychiatric situations in particular. This debate, which bears the seeds of a real desire to die as a personal choice, is likely to profoundly modify the doctor-patient relationship in the particular field of psychiatry.


Asunto(s)
Derecho a Morir , Suicidio Asistido , Muerte , Libertad , Humanos , Relaciones Médico-Paciente
13.
Nature ; 573(7773): 196, 2019 09.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31506626
14.
Palliat Med ; 34(5): 630-638, 2020 05.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32103705

RESUMEN

BACKGROUND: Some evidence suggests the wish to hasten death is related to poor health-related quality of life. Deficits in perceived dignity and self-efficacy are risk factors for wish to hasten death that also impact health-related quality of life. AIM: To compare perceived health-related quality of life, dignity and self-efficacy in patients with advanced cancer who either do (case group) or do not (control group) express a wish to hasten death. Cases and controls were matched on sociodemographic and functional characteristics. DESIGN: A comparative cross-sectional study. PARTICIPANTS: A total of 153 adult patients with advanced cancer were assessed for wish to hasten death using the Desire for Death Rating Scale. Scores ⩾1 indicate some degree of wish to hasten death (case group, n = 51), and score = 0 implies no wish to hasten death (control group, n = 102). Assessments included health-related quality of life using the European Organization for Research and Treatment of Cancer Quality-of-Life Core 15-Item Palliative Questionnaire, perceived loss of dignity using the Patient Dignity Inventory and self-efficacy using the General Self-Efficacy Scale. RESULTS: Patients with a wish to hasten death had worse emotional functioning (p < 0.001), greater perceived loss of dignity (p < 0.001) and lower self-efficacy (p = 0.001). There was no difference in most physical symptoms. Perceived overall health-related quality of life was significantly worse for those with a clinically relevant wish to hasten death (p = 0.023) and marginally worse for the case group than the control group (p = 0.052). CONCLUSION: Patients with wish to hasten death showed lower perceived dignity, self-efficacy and emotional quality of life than patients without wish to hasten death without necessarily perceiving worse physical symptoms.


Asunto(s)
Actitud Frente a la Muerte , Neoplasias/psicología , Calidad de Vida , Enfermo Terminal , Adulto , Estudios Transversales , Humanos , Cuidados Paliativos , Derecho a Morir
15.
J Med Ethics ; 46(6): 416-417, 2020 06.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32220872

RESUMEN

On 26 February 2020, the German Constitutional Court rejected a law from 2015 that prohibited any form of 'business-like' assisted suicide as unconstitutional. The landmark ruling of the highest federal court emphasised the high priority given to the rights of autonomy and free personal development, both of which constitute the principle of human dignity, the first principle of the German constitution. The ruling echoes particularities of post-war Germany's end-of-life debate focusing on patient self-determination while rejecting any discussion of active assistance to die through a lethal injection administered by a doctor. This brief report discusses the ruling in the light of the broader sociopolitical and historical context of the German end-of-life debate.


Asunto(s)
Eutanasia , Suicidio Asistido , Libertad , Humanos , Autonomía Personal , Derecho a Morir
16.
Bioethics ; 34(1): 135-141, 2020 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31410863

RESUMEN

Discussions about assisted suicide have hitherto been based on accounts of dignity conceived only as an inherent value or as a status; accounts of dignity in which it appears as a (contingent) attitude, by contrast, have been neglected. Yet there are two good reasons to consider dignity to be an attitude. First, this concept of dignity best allows us to grasp a crucial aspect of everyday language: people often express fears of losing their dignity-and it is not possible to explain this with an account in which dignity is inherent. Second, such a concept allows us to adduce new argumentation where the argument based on status ends. Dignity considered as a status provides grounds to argue for the moral permissibility of assisted suicide, in the sense that in such an account individuals possess the normative power to waive their right to life. But the question then remains of how to decide what counts as a good reason for assisted suicide-and this is where an argument based on dignity as an attitude can provide illumination.


Asunto(s)
Actitud , Respeto , Derecho a Morir/ética , Suicidio Asistido/psicología , Humanos , Autoimagen
17.
J Am Pharm Assoc (2003) ; 60(6): 874-879.e1, 2020.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32680783

RESUMEN

BACKGROUND: Medical aid-in-dying (AID) is increasingly available in the United States. Despite their substantial role in the medication use process, pharmacists' involvement in medical AID has been overlooked. OBJECTIVE: To describe pharmacist attitudes toward medical AID and experiences with Oregon's Death with Dignity Act (DWDA). METHODS: Qualitative analysis of Oregon-licensed pharmacists with professional interactions involving Oregon's DWDA. Data were collected through semistructured focus groups and analyzed with immersion-crystallization methods. RESULTS: Sixteen Oregon pharmacists participated in this study. The participants were almost evenly divided between males and females, who varied in age, years of pharmacy experience, and the number of DWDA encounters. Of these, 14 pharmacists agreed to participate in the DWDA process while 2 declined. Three themes emerged. First, pharmacists identified logistical challenges that negatively affected their ability to assist patients seeking medical AID. Second, pharmacists described the content and other patient counseling considerations for DWDA prescriptions. Third, pharmacists discussed how values and preferences informed their decisions related to medical AID requests. CONCLUSION: Pharmacists' involvement in medical AID has been largely focused on medication dispensing and patient counseling, and medical AID prescriptions raise unique challenges. Their decisions to participate were frequently tied to support for patient autonomy, although more research is needed to capture the diversity of attitudes, perspectives, and experiences related to their involvement with medical AID, particularly for those who decline to participate. There is a need to develop educational materials and other resources to assist pharmacists in navigating medical AID requests.


Asunto(s)
Servicios Farmacéuticos , Farmacias , Femenino , Humanos , Masculino , Oregon , Farmacéuticos , Rol Profesional , Derecho a Morir
18.
Qual Health Res ; 30(4): 572-582, 2020 03.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31274058

RESUMEN

Communication about organ donation at the time of imminent death is a meaningful, yet less understood, area of health communication. We employed a multiple goals framework to explore family normative perceptions of organ donation and the conversational goal tensions experienced during a family member's imminent death. Semi-structured interviews were conducted with 14 family members who refused to donate when approached by an organ procurement coordinator (OPC) upon the imminent death of a family member. Thematic analysis revealed that family members described their decisions to refuse donation as (a) last acts of love, (b) responses to unnecessary requests, and (c) consistent with the known beliefs of the patient. Participants described several goal tensions operating within the organ donation conversation itself, including (a) the management of frequent requests, (b) pressure to donate, and (c) enduring unwanted requests from the OPC. Communication goals frameworks offer practical insights for improving organ-related conversations.


Asunto(s)
Familia/psicología , Motivación , Apoderado/psicología , Negativa a Participar/psicología , Derecho a Morir , Obtención de Tejidos y Órganos , Adulto , Anciano , Toma de Decisiones , Femenino , Humanos , Masculino , Persona de Mediana Edad , Adulto Joven
19.
Appl Nurs Res ; 51: 151187, 2020 02.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31506183

RESUMEN

AIM: This study explored the attitudes, experiences, and perceptions of Korean nurses toward advance directives (ADs) before the establishment of new Well-Dying Law. METHODS: A sequential explanatory mixed method design was applied. We administered a constructed questionnaire on attitudes toward ADs and end-of-life issues and experience related to end-of-life decision-making. A Korean-translated version of the KAESAD [Knowledge-Attitudinal, Experimental Survey on ADs] was administered by 245 nurses. Semi-structured interviews (N = 16) were audio-recorded, transcribed, and coded in a qualitative content analysis. RESULTS: The quantitative results revealed the nurses' perspectives on ADs: that valuing patient's autonomy, authority, or rights is vital to the implementation of ADs and end-of-life decision-making. Also, nurses reported that patients should be knowledgeable and informed about ADs. These responses allowed us to generate an interview, which revealed four themes in adopting the Well-Dying Law, including ADs. Themes with 'benefits' and 'roles of health care providers' mainly supported the quantitative results. Themes with 'ethical issues,' such as disagreement between patients and family members on ADs, and 'preparation,' regarding adopting the new law, should be importantly considered when implementing ADs in clinical settings. CONCLUSIONS: Our study highlights that nurses need to develop sufficient knowledge on the laws, and communication skills to help patients be knowledgeable and make their own decisions regarding ADs. To successfully adopt the Well-Dying Law, our findings suggest that a nationwide public campaign and a continuing education program for nurses to manage ethical issues regarding ADs are required.


Asunto(s)
Directivas Anticipadas/legislación & jurisprudencia , Directivas Anticipadas/psicología , Actitud del Personal de Salud , Actitud Frente a la Muerte , Conocimientos, Actitudes y Práctica en Salud , Personal de Enfermería en Hospital/psicología , Derecho a Morir/legislación & jurisprudencia , Adulto , Femenino , Humanos , Masculino , República de Corea , Encuestas y Cuestionarios
20.
Palliat Support Care ; 18(5): 528-536, 2020 10.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32131932

RESUMEN

OBJECTIVE: Patients' desire to die (DD) is rarely discussed in palliative care (PC) due to health professionals' (HPs) feeling of uncertainty. The aim of the study was to develop and evaluate a training to increase HPs' self-confidence in responding professionally to patient's DD and to assess the feasibility of this approach. METHODS: The training course was developed via focus groups and relevant literature and refined with an advisory board. An evaluation design was developed to evaluate training outcomes and to examine feasibility. To assess self-confidence, knowledge, skills, and attitudes: (1) standardized surveys were applied at T1 (before training), T2 (directly after), and T3 (3 months later), and were analyzed by descriptive and non-parametric statistics; and (2) participants' open feedback was summarized by content. RESULTS: A two-day multi-disciplinary training was developed to improve self-confidence via diverse teaching methods. Twenty-four HPs from general and specialized PC were participated. Via self-rating on Likert scales at three time points, improvements were seen at T1, T2, and partly remained at T3, especially in the overall item of self-confidence in communicating with patients about their DD (means: 4.3. at T1, 5.7 at T2, and 5.9 at T3; on a 7-point scale with 1 = lowest value and 7 = highest value). Fewer improvements were found in skills (using different approaches) and attitudes (feeling less helplessness). Open feedback revealed a high appreciation for the training, especially the composition of participants, the role-play, and the overall increase of awareness of the topic. SIGNIFICANCE OF RESULTS: The developed training on addressing DD meets a need and was perceived by the participants to be of added value. Future research should measure training effects with a validated instrument, including more participants, diverse participant groups, and a control group. Effects on patients should be assessed.


Asunto(s)
Relaciones Profesional-Paciente , Derecho a Morir , Enseñanza/normas , Adulto , Curriculum/tendencias , Femenino , Grupos Focales/métodos , Humanos , Masculino , Persona de Mediana Edad , Evaluación de Necesidades , Proyectos Piloto , Investigación Cualitativa , Encuestas y Cuestionarios , Enseñanza/estadística & datos numéricos
SELECCIÓN DE REFERENCIAS
DETALLE DE LA BÚSQUEDA