Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Mostrar: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 13 de 13
Filtrar
1.
Med Health Care Philos ; 23(4): 735-742, 2020 Dec.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32566983

RESUMEN

Luck egalitarianism, a theory of distributive justice, holds that inequalities which arise due to individuals' imprudent choices must not, as a matter of justice, be neutralized. This article deals with the possible application of luck egalitarianism to the area of health care. It seeks to investigate whether the ethos of luck egalitarianism can be operationalized to the point of informing health care policy without straying from its own ideals. In the transition from theory to practise, luck egalitarianism encounters several difficulties. We argue that the charge of moral arbitrariness can, at least in part, be countered by our provided definition of "imprudent actions" in the health area. We discuss the choice for luck egalitarianism in health care between ex ante and ex post policy approaches, and show how both approaches are flawed by luck egalitarianism's own standards. We also examine the problem of threshold setting when luck egalitarianism is set to practise in health care. We argue that wherever policy thresholds are set, luck egalitarianism in health care risks pampering the imprudent, abandoning the prudent or, at worst, both. Furthermore, we claim that moves to mitigate these risks in turn diminish the normative importance of the ethos of luck egalitarianism to policy. All in all, our conclusion is that luck egalitarianism cannot be consistently applied as a convincing and relevant normative principle in health care policy.


Asunto(s)
Conductas Relacionadas con la Salud , Política de Salud , Asunción de Riesgos , Conducta de Elección , Asignación de Recursos para la Atención de Salud/ética , Humanos , Principios Morales , Filosofía Médica
2.
BMC Cancer ; 20(1): 401, 2020 May 08.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32384883

RESUMEN

BACKGROUND: Research and cancer care are closely intertwined; however, it is not clear whether physicians and nurses believe that clinical trials offer the best treatment for patients and, if so, whether this belief is justified. The aim of this study was therefore: (i) to explore how physicians and nurses perceive the benefits of clinical trial participation compared with standard care and (ii) whether it is justified to claim that clinical trial participation improves outcomes for cancer patients. METHODS: A mixed methods approach was used employing semi-structured interviews with 57 physicians and nurses in oncology and haematology and a literature review of the evidence for trial superiority, i.e. the idea that receiving treatment in a clinical trial leads to a better outcome compared with standard care. Inductive thematic analysis was used to examine the interview data. A literature review comprising nine articles was conducted according to a conceptual framework developed by Peppercorn et al. and evaluated recent evidence on trial superiority. RESULTS: Our findings show that many physicians and nurses make claims supporting trial superiority, however very little evidence is available in the literature comparing outcomes for trial participants and non-participants that supports their assertions. CONCLUSIONS: Despite the recent rapid development and use of targeted therapy and immunotherapy, we find no support for trial participation to provide better outcomes for cancer patients than standard care. Hence, our present results are in line with previous results from Peppercorn et al. A weaker version of the superiority claim is that even if a trial does not bring about a direct positive effect, it brings about indirect positive effects. However, as the value of such indirect effects is dependent on the individual's specific circumstances and preferences, their existence cannot establish the general claim that treatment in trials is superior. Belief in trial superiority is therefore unfounded. Hence, if such beliefs are communicated to patients in a trial recruitment context, it would provide misleading information. Instead emphasis should be on patients volunteering to give an altruistic contribution to the furthering of knowledge and to the potential benefit of future patients.


Asunto(s)
Ensayos Clínicos como Asunto/estadística & datos numéricos , Personal de Salud/psicología , Neoplasias/terapia , Evaluación de Resultado en la Atención de Salud , Participación del Paciente , Proyectos de Investigación , Adulto , Actitud del Personal de Salud , Femenino , Humanos , Masculino , Persona de Mediana Edad , Modelos Teóricos , Selección de Paciente , Resultado del Tratamiento
3.
Support Care Cancer ; 27(9): 3555-3561, 2019 Sep.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30689045

RESUMEN

PURPOSE: To examine whether experiences of positive respectful encounters and negative disrespectful encounters differ between sickness absentees with a cancer diagnosis and sickness absentees with other diagnoses, especially in relation to their ability to return to work (RTW). METHODS: A total of 9032 long-term sickness absentees in Sweden responded to a questionnaire (response rate 52%) about experiences of positive and negative encounters with healthcare professionals. The association between different types of such encounters and participants feeling respected or disrespected were calculated with population attributable risk with 95% confidence intervals (CI). The perceived impact on ability to RTW was also examined. RESULTS: Significantly, larger proportions among those who experienced a positive encounter and also felt respected stated that those encounters facilitated their ability to RTW, compared to those who experienced a positive encounter without feeling respected: among cancer absentees the difference in proportions were 21% (CI, 7-34) versus 50% (CI, 45-55); among absentees with other diagnoses 42% (CI, 37-47) versus 63% (CI, 61-64). Similar comparisons among sick-listed who experienced negative encounters indicated that also feeling disrespected impeded ability to RTW among a significantly larger proportion of those with other diagnoses [51% (CI, 48-54) versus 35% (CI, 31-39) of those not feeling disrespected]. Among cancer absentees, the corresponding proportions were 20% (CI, 9-30) versus 25% (CI, 9-41). CONCLUSIONS: Compared to sickness absentees with other diagnoses, a larger proportion of cancer sickness absentees stated that they were facilitated by respectful encounters and not impeded by disrespectful encounters, regarding self-estimated ability to RTW. More research is needed to examine whether these differences can be associated with use of a patient-centered encountering approach.


Asunto(s)
Neoplasias/terapia , Relaciones Profesional-Paciente , Reinserción al Trabajo/estadística & datos numéricos , Ausencia por Enfermedad/estadística & datos numéricos , Absentismo , Adulto , Impedancia Eléctrica , Emociones , Femenino , Personal de Salud , Humanos , Masculino , Persona de Mediana Edad , Encuestas y Cuestionarios , Suecia , Adulto Joven
4.
J Med Ethics ; 45(1): 26-30, 2019 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30266796

RESUMEN

Psychiatry today is mainly practised within a curative framework. However, many mental disorders are persistent and negatively affect quality of life as well as life expectancy. This tension between treatment goals and the actual illness trajectory has evoked a growing academic interest in 'palliative psychiatry', namely the application of a palliative care approach in patients with severe persistent mental illness. Recently, Trachsel et al presented a working definition of palliative psychiatry. This first official attempt to capture the concept is based on WHO's widely accepted definition of palliative care but modified and limited to include only severe persistent psychiatric illness. While this is a welcome step in the discussion on palliative care approaches in psychiatry, it also opens up for new questions. One of the most evident is whether psychiatry actually needs its own definition of palliative care or, put differently, whether there is something about mental disorders that differs so radically from other medical conditions that it calls for a separate definition. We acknowledge the need to discuss the goals of psychiatric care in patients with severe persistent psychiatric illness. However, we question whether a separate definition of palliative care exclusive to psychiatry is the right way to go. In this paper, we discuss why.


Asunto(s)
Trastornos Mentales/terapia , Cuidados Paliativos , Psiquiatría/métodos , Humanos , Planificación de Atención al Paciente , Terminología como Asunto
5.
J Empir Res Hum Res Ethics ; 9(4): 1-9, 2014 Oct.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25747292

RESUMEN

There are an increasing number of medical research studies involving children, including many long-term birth cohort studies. Involving children raises many issues, and little is known about children's own views. This study explored children's views (N = 5,851) on participation in a long-term screening study for type 1 diabetes. The results show that children 10 to 13 years of age have in general a positive attitude to pediatric research and emphasized trust in researchers. The children stressed the importance to receive information and to be involved in decisions. The children also reported feeling concerned about blood sampling and disease risk. Researchers involved in long-term pediatric research need to address these issues to promote involvement and decrease worry.


Asunto(s)
Actitud , Diabetes Mellitus Tipo 1 , Tamizaje Masivo , Sujetos de Investigación , Investigación , Adolescente , Niño , Estudios de Cohortes , Diabetes Mellitus Tipo 1/diagnóstico , Emociones , Femenino , Humanos , Estudios Longitudinales , Masculino , Participación del Paciente , Sujetos de Investigación/psicología , Confianza
6.
Med Health Care Philos ; 16(2): 225-30, 2013 May.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22161026

RESUMEN

Respect for autonomy is typically considered a key reason for allowing physician assisted suicide and euthanasia. However, several recent papers have claimed this to be grounded in a misconception of the normative relevance of autonomy. It has been argued that autonomy is properly conceived of as a value, and that this makes assisted suicide as well as euthanasia wrong, since they destroy the autonomy of the patient. This paper evaluates this line of reasoning by investigating the conception of valuable autonomy. Starting off from the current debate in end-of-life care, two different interpretations of how autonomy is valuable is discussed. According to one interpretation, autonomy is a personal prudential value, which may provide a reason why euthanasia and assisted suicide might be against a patient's best interests. According to a second interpretation, inspired by Kantian ethics, being autonomous is unconditionally valuable, which may imply a duty to preserve autonomy. We argue that both lines of reasoning have limitations when it comes to situations relevant for end-of life care. It is concluded that neither way of reasoning can be used to show that assisted suicide or euthanasia always is impermissible.


Asunto(s)
Eutanasia/psicología , Cuidados Paliativos , Autonomía Personal , Suicidio Asistido/psicología , Eutanasia/ética , Humanos , Paternalismo , Filosofía Médica , Suicidio Asistido/ética
7.
BMJ Support Palliat Care ; 3(2): 203-6, 2013 Jun.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24644569

RESUMEN

In palliative care there is much debate about which end of life treatment strategies are legitimate and which are not. Some writers argue that there is an important moral dividing-line between palliative sedation and euthanasia, making the first acceptable and the latter not. We have questioned this. In a recent article, Lars Johan Materstvedt has argued that we are wrong on two accounts: first, that we fail to account properly for the moral difference between continuous deep palliative sedation at the end of life and euthanasia, and, second, that we fail to account properly for the difference between permanent loss of consciousness and death. Regarding the first objection, we argue that Materstvedt misses the point: we agree that there is a difference in terms of intentions between continuous deep palliative sedation and euthanasia, but we question whether this conceptual difference makes up for a moral difference. Materstvedt fails to show that it does. Regarding the second objection, we argue that if nothing else is at stake than the value of the patient's life, permanent unconsciousness and death are morally indifferent.


Asunto(s)
Sedación Profunda/métodos , Sedación Profunda/psicología , Eutanasia/psicología , Principios Morales , Cuidados Paliativos/métodos , Cuidados Paliativos/psicología , Actitud del Personal de Salud , Humanos , Intención
8.
J Med Ethics ; 38(4): 247-9, 2012 Apr.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22138726

RESUMEN

Many countries are now implementing human papillomavirus vaccination. There is disagreement about who should receive the vaccine. Some propose vaccinating both boys and girls in order to achieve the largest possible public health impact. Others regard this approach as too costly and claim that only girls should be vaccinated. We question the assumption that decisions about human papillomavirus vaccination policy should rely solely on estimates of overall benefits and costs. There are important social justice aspects that also need to be considered. Policy makers should consider how to best protect individuals who will remain unvaccinated through no fault of their own. This is especially important if these individuals are already disadvantaged in other ways and if vaccinating other people increases their risk of infection.


Asunto(s)
Programas de Inmunización/ética , Infecciones por Papillomavirus/prevención & control , Vacunas contra Papillomavirus/economía , Neoplasias del Cuello Uterino/prevención & control , Análisis Costo-Beneficio/ética , Femenino , Humanos , Masculino , Infecciones por Papillomavirus/virología , Vacunas contra Papillomavirus/uso terapéutico , Salud Pública/ética , Factores Sexuales , Justicia Social , Neoplasias del Cuello Uterino/virología , Vacunación/ética
9.
Camb Q Healthc Ethics ; 20(3): 409-17, 2011 Jul.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-21676328

RESUMEN

A wide variety of bioethical themes have recently been debated and researched in Sweden, including genetic screening, HPV vaccination strategies, end-of-life care, injustices and priority setting in healthcare, dual-use research, and the never-ending story of scientific fraud. Also, there are some new events related to Swedish biobanking that might be of general interest. Here we will concentrate on four themes: end-of-life care, dual-use research, scientific fraud, and biobanking.


Asunto(s)
Ética en Investigación , Consentimiento Informado/ética , Cuidados Paliativos/ética , Derecho a Morir/ética , Mala Conducta Científica/ética , Cuidado Terminal/ética , Bancos de Tejidos/ética , Comités Consultivos , Analgesia/ética , Discusiones Bioéticas , Bioética/educación , Sedación Profunda/ética , Principio del Doble Efecto , Humanos , Derecho a Morir/legislación & jurisprudencia , Suicidio Asistido/ética , Suecia , Bancos de Tejidos/legislación & jurisprudencia , Privación de Tratamiento/ética
10.
Med Health Care Philos ; 14(1): 19-27, 2011 Feb.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-20853152

RESUMEN

Human papillomavirus (HPV) infection is the world's most common sexually transmitted infection. It is a prerequisite for cervical cancer, the second most common cause of death in cancer among women worldwide, and is also believed to cause other anogenital and head and neck cancers. Vaccines that protect against the most common cancer-causing HPV types have recently become available, and different countries have taken different approaches to implementing vaccination. This paper examines the ethics of alternative HPV vaccination strategies. It devotes particular attention to the major arguments for and against one strategy: voluntary, publicly funded vaccination for all adolescent boys and girls. This approach seems attractive because it would protect more people against cervical cancer and other HPV-related cancers than less inclusive alternatives, without the sacrifice of autonomy that a comparably broad compulsory programme would require. Also, the herd immunity that it would likely generate would protect those who remain unvaccinated, a major advantage from a justice perspective. However, there is a possibility that a HPV vaccination programme targeting all adolescents of both sexes is not considered sufficiently cost-effective. Also, it might pose more difficulties for achieving informed consent than comparable vaccination programmes against other diseases. Ultimately, society's choice of HPV vaccination strategy requires careful consideration not only of the values at stake but also of available and emerging scientific evidence.


Asunto(s)
Programas de Inmunización/ética , Infecciones por Papillomavirus/prevención & control , Vacunas contra Papillomavirus/administración & dosificación , Neoplasias del Cuello Uterino/prevención & control , Adolescente , Comparación Transcultural , Países Desarrollados , Femenino , Humanos , Inmunidad Colectiva/efectos de los fármacos , Programas de Inmunización/organización & administración , Masculino , Justicia Social , Neoplasias del Cuello Uterino/etiología , Neoplasias del Cuello Uterino/virología
11.
Med Health Care Philos ; 13(1): 59-65, 2010 Feb.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-19672696

RESUMEN

In a Swedish setting physicians are unlikely to give explicitly paternalistic reasons when asked about their attitudes towards patients' involvement in decision-making. There is considerable risk that they will disguise their paternalism by giving 'socially correct answers'. We suggest that disguised paternalism can be revealed with the help of indexes based on certain responses in postal questionnaires. The indexes were developed using material from a study examining attitudes of Swedish physicians to physician-assisted suicide (PAS). Apart from being asked about their attitudes, they were asked to prioritize between different arguments for and against PAS. One argument for PAS was: "PAS should be permitted out of respect for patients' autonomy". One argument against PAS was: "PAS should not be permitted since the non-maleficence principle in this case takes precedence over respecting patients' autonomy". Responses to the latter argument formed the cornerstone of a disguised-paternalism index, while an autonomy index was based on answers to the former argument. Applying our indexes to data from the PAS survey, we found that female GPs, surgeons, and older male physicians were least paternalistic. Among female physicians one finds both the most autonomy-respecting groups (female surgeons and GPs) and the least autonomy-respecting groups (female oncologists and psychiatrists); together with older male physicians in general, female GPs are the group displaying least disguised paternalism. We suggest that questionnaires exploring paternalism might be improved by including case-specific questions or statements by which to explore disguised paternalism. Here our indexes might be useful tools.


Asunto(s)
Actitud del Personal de Salud , Paternalismo , Médicos/psicología , Suicidio Asistido/psicología , Adulto , Factores de Edad , Anciano , Anciano de 80 o más Años , Femenino , Humanos , Masculino , Persona de Mediana Edad , Cuidados Paliativos/organización & administración , Participación del Paciente/psicología , Factores Sexuales , Suecia
12.
Lancet Oncol ; 7(3): 266-9, 2006 Mar.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-16510336

RESUMEN

Large international biobank studies can make substantial contributions to scientific research by validation of the biological importance of previous research and by identification of previously unknown causes of disease. However, regulations for patient consent that are too strict and discrepancies in national policies on informed consent might hinder progress. Therefore, establishment of common ground for ethical review of biobank research is essential. In this essay, broad consent is defined on a scale between strictly specified (eg, for a specific study) and blanket consent (ie, with no restrictions regarding the purpose of the research). Future research includes that which might not be planned or even conceptualised when consent is obtained. In conclusion, broad consent and consent for future research are valid ethically and should be recommended for biobank research provided that: personal information related to research is handled safely; donors of biological samples are granted the right to withdraw consent; and new research studies or changes to the legal or ethical authority of a biobank are approved by an ethics-review board.


Asunto(s)
Consentimiento Informado , Bancos de Tejidos/ética , Donantes de Tejidos , Confidencialidad , Ética Médica , Predisposición Genética a la Enfermedad , Humanos , Investigación
13.
Eur J Hum Genet ; 13(3): 376-83, 2005 Mar.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-15657607

RESUMEN

This empirical study explores participants' perceptions of information and understanding of their children's and their own involvement in a longitudinal screening, the ABIS Study. ABIS (All Babies In Southeast Sweden) is a multicentre, longitudinal research screening for Type 1 diabetes and multifactorial diseases involving 17 005 children and their families. For this study, a random selection of mothers was made, using perinatal questionnaire serial numbers from the ABIS study. In total, 293 of these mothers completed an anonymous questionnaire (response rate 73.3%). Our findings from the questionnaire indicate a marked difference between the reported satisfaction with and understanding of the information provided on the one hand and the significant lack of knowledge of some of the aims and methods of the ABIS screening on the other, namely concerning high-risk identification of involved children, potential prevention and future questionnaires. Two questions evoked by our results are: (1) what information is required for participants in longitudinal studies involving children? and (2) how do we ensure and sustain understanding, and thus in a prolonging, informed consent in these studies? This study underlines the importance of an increased understanding of the ethical issues that longitudinal research on children raise and the need to discuss how information and informed consent strategies should be analysed and designed in longitudinal studies.


Asunto(s)
Ética en Investigación , Consentimiento Informado , Estudios Longitudinales , Madres , Adulto , Niño , Diabetes Mellitus Tipo 1/diagnóstico , Diabetes Mellitus Tipo 1/prevención & control , Femenino , Conocimientos, Actitudes y Práctica en Salud , Humanos , Lactante , Recién Nacido , Tamizaje Masivo , Recuerdo Mental , Estudios Multicéntricos como Asunto/ética , Factores de Riesgo , Encuestas y Cuestionarios , Suecia
SELECCIÓN DE REFERENCIAS
DETALLE DE LA BÚSQUEDA