Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 20 de 244
Filter
Add more filters

Publication year range
1.
Med Health Care Philos ; 27(2): 189-203, 2024 Jun.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38363499

ABSTRACT

This paper critically engages with how life not worth living (LNWL) and cognate concepts are used in the field of beginning-of-life bioethics as the basis of arguments for morally requiring the application of preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) and/or germline genome editing (GGE). It is argued that an objective conceptualization of LNWL is largely too unreliable in beginning-of-life cases for deriving decisive normative reasons that would constitute a moral duty on the part of intending parents. Subjective frameworks are found to be more suitable to determine LNWL, but they are not accessible in beginning-of-life cases because there is no subject yet. Conceptual and sociopolitical problems are additionally pointed out regarding the common usage of clear case exemplars. The paper concludes that a moral requirement for the usage of PGD and GGE cannot be derived from the conceptual base of LNWL, as strong reasons that can be reliably determined are required to limit reproductive freedom on moral grounds. Educated predictions on prospective well-being might still be useful regarding the determination of moral permissibility of PGD and/or GGE. It is suggested that due to the high significance of subjective experience in the normativity of beginning-of-life bioethics, the discipline is called to more actively realize the inclusion of people with disabilities. This regards for instance research design, citation practices, and language choices to increase the accessibility of societal debates on the reproductive ethics of genetic technologies.


Subject(s)
Gene Editing , Preimplantation Diagnosis , Reproductive Techniques, Assisted , Humans , Reproductive Techniques, Assisted/ethics , Reproductive Techniques, Assisted/psychology , Preimplantation Diagnosis/ethics , Gene Editing/ethics , Bioethics , Value of Life , Moral Obligations , Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Morals , Philosophy, Medical
2.
Development ; 144(14): 2541-2543, 2017 07 15.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-28720650

ABSTRACT

Research into human development involves the use of human embryos and their derivative cells and tissues. How religions view the human embryo depends on beliefs about ensoulment and the inception of personhood, and science can neither prove nor refute the teaching of those religions that consider the zygote to be a human person with an immortal soul. This Spotlight article discusses some of the dominant themes that have emerged with regard to how different religions view the human embryo, with a focus on the Christian faith as well as Buddhist, Hindu, Jewish and Islamic perspectives.


Subject(s)
Beginning of Human Life , Embryo, Mammalian , Personhood , Religion and Medicine , Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Embryo Research/ethics , Humans , Stem Cell Research/ethics
3.
J Med Philos ; 45(3): 371-386, 2020 05 21.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32437577

ABSTRACT

When did we begin to exist? Barry Smith and Berit Brogaard argue that a new human organism comes into existence neither earlier nor later than the moment of gastrulation: 16 days after conception. Several critics have responded that the onset of the organism must happen earlier; closer to conception. This article makes a radically different claim: if we accept Smith and Brogaard's ontological commitments, then human organisms start, on average, roughly nine months after conception. The main point of contention is whether the fetus is or is not part of the maternal organism. Smith and Brogaard argue that it is not; I demonstrate that it is. This claim in combination with Smith and Brogaard's own criteria commits to the view that human organisms begin, precisely, at birth.


Subject(s)
Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Personhood , Philosophy, Medical , Embryo, Mammalian/physiology , Fetus/physiology , Humans , Parturition/physiology , Parturition/psychology
4.
J Med Ethics ; 45(5): 304-308, 2019 05.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30796091

ABSTRACT

Opposition to induced abortion rests on the belief that fetuses have a moral status comparable to beings like us, and that the loss of such a life is tragic. Antiabortion, or pro-life, theorists argue that (1) it is wrong to induce abortion and (2) it is wrong to allow others to perform induced abortion. However, evidence suggests that spontaneous abortion kills far more fetuses than induced abortion, and critics argue that most pro-life theorists neglect the threat of spontaneous abortion and ought to do more to prevent it. Friberg-Fernros contends such an obligation would be implausibly strong, arguing that induced abortions are far worse than spontaneous abortions because while both involve the tragedy of the death of the fetus, induced abortion involves a second tragedy-one person killing another. I argue this two tragedies argument fails to explain what is morally relevant about induced abortion.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced/ethics , Abortion, Spontaneous/epidemiology , Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Human Rights/ethics , Value of Life , Dissent and Disputes , Female , Humans , Personhood , Philosophy, Medical , Pregnancy
5.
Bioethics ; 33(9): 1035-1041, 2019 11.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31452225

ABSTRACT

The somatic integration definition of life is familiar from the debate on the determination of death, with some bioethicists arguing that it supports brain death while others argue that some brain-dead bodies exhibit sufficient somatic integration for biological life. I argue that on either interpretation, the somatic integration definition of life implies that neither the preimplantation embryo nor the postimplantation embryo meet the somatic integration threshold condition for organismal human life. The earliest point at which a somatic integration determination of life could be made would be the beginning of the fetal stage, 9 weeks postfertilization. Bioethical implications are considered, specifically with respect to the moral status of the postimplantation embryo in embryo research and abortion.


Subject(s)
Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Bioethical Issues , Ethics, Medical , Fetal Development , Moral Obligations , Value of Life , Adult , Female , Humans , Male , Pregnancy
6.
Bioethics ; 33(4): 529-535, 2019 05.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-30681177

ABSTRACT

When a human being comes into existence is crucial in bioethics. Conceptionism is the view that a human being comes into existence at conception. The twinning argument is an influential objection to this view. All versions of the twinning argument rely on a metaphysics of material objects, namely, endurantism. Given this, a strategy for defending conceptionism against the twinning argument is to deny endurantism and adopt an alternative metaphysics of material objects. A version of this strategy which has been debated in this journal is to adopt perdurantism, or the 'multiple occupancy view', on which monozygotic twins share the zygote region as a temporal part. We present a novel version of this strategy: conceptionists can evade the twinning argument by adopting an exdurantist metaphysics of material objects. We suggest reasons for thinking that this is a plausible and, indeed, preferable way for conceptionists to avoid the twinning argument.


Subject(s)
Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Dissent and Disputes , Fertilization , Metaphysics , Personhood , Bioethics , Ethical Theory , Humans , Philosophy , Theology , Zygote
7.
J Med Philos ; 43(2): 132-158, 2018 Mar 13.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-29546412

ABSTRACT

Moral status ascribes equal obligations and rights to individuals on the basis of membership in a protected group. Substance change is an event that results in the origin or cessation of individuals who may be members of groups with equal moral status. In this paper, two substance changes that affect the moral status of human embryos are identified. The first substance change begins with fertilization and ends with the formation of the blastocyst, a biological individual with moral status comparable to that ascribed to human organs. The second substance change begins at implantation and ends late in embryological development with the formation of the human body, an organism with moral status as a human being. The bioethical implications of each substance change are explored. The Two Substance Change theory is contrasted with continuity theories, which recognize no substance change in embryological development and with fertilization-only substance change theories.


Subject(s)
Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Embryo, Mammalian , Moral Status , Abortion, Induced/ethics , Bioethical Issues , Blastocyst , Fertilization , Humans , Morals , Value of Life
8.
Psychiatr Danub ; 29 Suppl 1: 89-91, 2017 04.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-28468027

ABSTRACT

One of the most controversial topics in modern bioethics, science, and philosophy is the beginning of individual human life. In the seemingly endless debate, strongly stimulated by recent technologic advances in human reproduction, a synthesis between scientific data and hypothesis, philosophical thought, and issues of humanities has become a necessity to deal with ethical, juridical, and social problems. Furthermore, in this field there is a temptation to ask science to choose between opinions and beliefs, which neutralize one another. The question of when human life begins requires the essential aid of different forms of knowledge. Here we become involved in the juncture between science and religion, which needs to be carefully explored.


Subject(s)
Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Conflict, Psychological , Religion and Science , Bioethics , Biological Evolution , Ethics, Medical , Female , Fertilization/physiology , Fetus/physiology , Humans , Infant, Newborn , Philosophy, Medical , Pregnancy
9.
Bioethics ; 30(9): 656-662, 2016 11.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27717058

ABSTRACT

Alberto Giubilini and Francesca Minerva's controversial article 'After-Birth Abortion: Why Should the Baby Live?' has received a lot of criticism since its publishing. Part of the recent criticism has been made by pro-life philosopher Christopher Kaczor, who argues against infanticide in his updated book 'Ethics of Abortion'. Kaczor makes four arguments to show where Giubilini and Minerva's argument for permitting infanticide goes wrong. In this article I argue that Kaczor's arguments, and some similar arguments presented by other philosophers, are mistaken and cannot show Giubilini and Minerva's view to be flawed. I claim that if one wants to reject the permissibility of infanticide, one must find better arguments for doing so.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced/ethics , Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Infanticide/ethics , Moral Obligations , Personhood , Adoption , Female , Fetal Viability , Humans , Infant, Newborn , Pregnancy , Value of Life
10.
J Med Ethics ; 41(6): 460-3, 2015 Jun.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25012846

ABSTRACT

What role does birth play in the debate about elective abortion? Does the wrongness of infanticide imply the wrongness of late-term abortion? In this paper, I argue that the same or similar factors that make birth morally significant with regard to abortion make meaningful viability morally significant due to the relatively arbitrary time of birth. I do this by considering the positions of Mary Anne Warren and José Luis Bermúdez who argue that birth is significant enough that the wrongness of infanticide does not imply the wrongness of late-term abortion. On the basis of the relatively arbitrary timing of birth, I argue that meaningful viability is the point at which elective abortion is prima facie morally wrong.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Criminal/ethics , Abortion, Induced/ethics , Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Fetal Viability , Morals , Parturition , Female , Humans , Moral Obligations , Personhood , Pregnancy , Value of Life
11.
Health Care Anal ; 23(1): 1-18, 2015 Mar.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23076345

ABSTRACT

There is a fundamental inconsistency in Western society's treatment of non-human animals on the one hand, and of human foetuses on the other. While most Western countries allow the butchering of animals and their use in experimentation, this must occur under carefully controlled conditions that are intended to minimize their pain and suffering as much as possible. At the same time, most Western countries permit various abortion methods without similar concerns for the developing fetus. The only criteria for deciding which abortion method is used centre in the stage of the pregnancy, the size of the fetus, the health of the pregnant woman and the physician's preference. This is out of step with the underlying ethos of animal cruelty legislation, cannot be justified ethically and should be rectified by adjusting abortion methods to the capacity of the fetus to experience nociception and/or pain.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced/ethics , Abortion, Induced/methods , Ethics, Medical , Animal Welfare/legislation & jurisprudence , Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Female , Human Rights , Humans , Morals , Pregnancy , Pregnant Women
12.
Med Law Rev ; 23(4): 588-619, 2015.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-26232721

ABSTRACT

The Report of the Committee of Inquiry into Human Fertilisation and Embryology, the Warnock Report, forms the basis of the UK legislation on embryo research, and its influence continues to be felt, even though over 30 years have passed since its publication. The Warnock Committee was the first of its kind to consider how advancements in human fertilisation and embryology should be regulated. This article examines the evidence submitted to the Warnock Committee, upon which its members ultimately reached their conclusions. With ongoing debate as to the status of the human embryo, it is important to recognise that the legislative position is one that was reached after extensive consultation and consideration of submitted evidence by the Warnock Committee. This article considers the differing ethical viewpoints that were expressed by organisations both prior and post-publication of the Warnock Report, and how the Committee used that evidence to reach their conclusions, and ultimately calls for a new Warnock-style committee.


Subject(s)
Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Embryo Research/legislation & jurisprudence , Technology Assessment, Biomedical/legislation & jurisprudence , Advisory Committees , Bioethics , Embryo Research/ethics , Government Regulation , Humans , Informed Consent/ethics , Personhood , Religion and Medicine , Technology Assessment, Biomedical/ethics , Technology Assessment, Biomedical/methods , United Kingdom
13.
J Med Ethics ; 40(6): 392-5, 2014 Jun.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23760578

ABSTRACT

Anja Karnein has suggested that because of the importance of respect for persons, law and policy should require some human embryos created in vitro to be available for adoption for a period of time. If no one comes forward to adopt the embryos during that time, they may be destroyed (in the case of embryos left over from fertility medicine) or used in research (in the case of embryos created for that purpose or left over from fertility medicine). This adoption option would increase the number of embryos available for couples looking for help in having children, but that effect is less important--Karnein argues--than the observance of respect for human persons. As possible persons, she holds that embryos ought to be treated, as if they will become children, if only for a while. If enacted as a matter of law and policy, an 'adoption option' would wrongly interfere with the dispositional rights women and men ought to have over embryos they create in the course of trying to have children. Karnein's proposal would also deprive researchers of certainty that the embryos they create for research would actually be available that way, leading to increased burdens of time and money and maybe even to more embryos than would otherwise be produced. Karnein's analysis does not show, moreover, that any duty of rescue applies to embryos. No woman is required to adopt any embryo, which significantly undercuts the justification for an obligatory adoption period.


Subject(s)
Adoption/legislation & jurisprudence , Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Embryo Transfer/ethics , Fertilization in Vitro/ethics , Ethics, Medical , Female , Humans , Male
14.
J Med Ethics ; 40(4): 284-5, 2014 Apr.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23709176

ABSTRACT

Following the debate in the UK House of Lords, in December 2012, uncertainty remains as to the manner in which human and non-human interspecies embryos are differentiated in law.


Subject(s)
Embryo Research/legislation & jurisprudence , Embryo, Mammalian , Government Regulation , Moral Obligations , Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Embryo Research/ethics , Humans , Uncertainty , United Kingdom
15.
J Med Ethics ; 40(12): 849-53, 2014 Dec.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24335584

ABSTRACT

Medical ethics forms an essential component of an undergraduate medical programme. In the UK the Institute of Medical Ethics has released a consensus statement detailing its recommendations for a minimum curriculum for ethics. One important issue it highlights for inclusion is 'Beginning of Life', which includes a wide range of themes. This paper presents an evaluation of the current teaching and assessment of these important issues in UK medical schools, complemented by a specific analysis of students' reaction to the teaching they received at the University of Edinburgh as part of their Obstetrics and Gynaecology rotation. Schools which responded to the survey reported a wide range of teaching and assessment methods. While there was a good overall coverage of topics, only one of them was covered by every institution and the religious/cultural elements of those topics were often neglected. The medical schools viewed better clinical integration of ethics teaching as the best route to improvement, but the students reported a desire for more ethics teaching in the form of specific tutorials, lectures or discussions. It is likely that a combination of these approaches will lead to significant improvements in the delivery of ethics teaching in this area and in others.


Subject(s)
Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Curriculum , Education, Medical, Undergraduate , Ethics, Medical/education , Consensus , Curriculum/standards , Curriculum/trends , Education, Medical, Undergraduate/standards , Education, Medical, Undergraduate/trends , Female , Gynecology/education , Humans , Male , Needs Assessment , Obstetrics/education , Schools, Medical/standards , Schools, Medical/trends , Scotland , Students, Medical/statistics & numerical data , Surveys and Questionnaires , United Kingdom , Young Adult
16.
Bioethics ; 28(8): 420-6, 2014 Oct.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23445499

ABSTRACT

The debate concerning the moral permissibility of using human embryos in human embryonic stem cell (hESC) research has long centred on the question of the embryo's supposed right to life. However, in focussing only on this question, many opponents to hESC research have escaped rigorous scrutiny by making vague and unfounded appeals to the concept of moral respect in order to justify their opposition to certain hESC practices. In this paper, I offer a critical analysis of the concept of moral respect, and its use to support the intuitively appealing principle of proportionality in hESC research. I argue that if proponents of this principle are to justify its adoption by appealing to the concept of moral respect, they must explain two things concerning the nature of the moral respect owed to embryos. First, they must explain which particular aspect of the embryo is morally relevant, and why. Second, they must explain why some uses of embryos in research fail to acknowledge what is morally relevant about the embryo, and thereby involve a violation of the moral respect that they are due. I shall show that providing such explanations may be more difficult than it first appears.


Subject(s)
Embryo Research/ethics , Embryo, Mammalian , Moral Obligations , Personhood , Stem Cell Research/ethics , Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Dissent and Disputes , Ethics, Research , Humans , Value of Life
17.
Kennedy Inst Ethics J ; 24(4): 345-84, 2014 Dec.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25638947

ABSTRACT

This essay argues that the polarization of our public debate over embryo-destructive research may be due, to a large extent, not to different valuations of individual human life but to different conceptions of the process of gestation, with one group treating the process as a making or construction and the other treating it as a development. These two incompatible models of reproduction are shown to explain the various positions commonly encountered in this debate over the treatment of embryos, and to a significant degree those encountered in the debate over abortion as well. Finally, the historical, theoretical, and intuitive strengths of each model are examined.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Induced , Beginning of Human Life , Embryonic Development , Fetal Development , Pregnancy , Abortion, Induced/ethics , Abortion, Induced/legislation & jurisprudence , Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Comprehension , Dissent and Disputes , Embryo Research/ethics , Ethical Analysis , Ethical Theory , Female , Germany , Humans , Jurisprudence , Models, Theoretical , Semantics , Stem Cell Research/ethics , United States
18.
BMC Med Ethics ; 15: 10, 2014 Feb 05.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24499356

ABSTRACT

BACKGROUND: Approximately one-fourth of all the inhabitants on earth are Muslims. Due to unprecedented migration, physicians are often confronted with cultures other than their own that adhere to different paradigms. DISCUSSION: In Islam, and most religions, abortion is forbidden. Islam is considerably liberal concerning abortion, which is dependent on (i) the threat of harm to mothers, (ii) the status of the pregnancy before or after ensoulment (on the 120th day of gestation), and (iii) the presence of foetal anomalies that are incompatible with life. Considerable variation in religious edicts exists, but most Islamic scholars agree that the termination of a pregnancy for foetal anomalies is allowed before ensoulment, after which abortion becomes totally forbidden, even in the presence of foetal abnormalities; the exception being a risk to the mother's life or confirmed intrauterine death. SUMMARY: The authors urge Muslim law makers to also consider abortion post ensoulment if it is certain that the malformed foetus will decease soon after birth or will be severely malformed and physically and mentally incapacitated after birth to avoid substantial hardship that may continue for years for mothers and family members. The authors recommend that an institutional committee governed and monitored by a national committee make decisions pertaining to abortion to ensure that ethics are preserved and mistakes are prevented. Anomalous foetuses must be detected at the earliest possible time to enable an appropriate medical intervention prior to the 120th day.


Subject(s)
Abortion, Therapeutic/ethics , Beginning of Human Life , Congenital Abnormalities , Islam , Mothers/psychology , Policy Making , Religion and Medicine , Abortion, Therapeutic/psychology , Attitude to Health , Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Delayed Diagnosis , Female , Fetal Development , Gestational Age , Guidelines as Topic , Humans , Infant, Newborn , Male , Pregnancy , Pregnancy Complications
19.
J Med Ethics ; 39(8): 537-40, 2013 Aug.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23292218

ABSTRACT

I defend the argument that if embryo loss in stem cell research is morally problematic, then embryo loss in in vivo conception is similarly morally problematic. According to a recent challenge to this argument, we can distinguish between in vivo embryo loss and the in vitro embryo loss of stem cell research by appealing to the doctrine of double effect. I argue that this challenge fails to show that in vivo embryo loss is a mere unintended side effect while in vitro embryo loss is an intended means and that, even if we refine the challenge by appealing to Michael Bratman's three roles of intention, the distinction is still unwarranted.


Subject(s)
Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Embryo Loss , Embryo Research/ethics , Embryo, Mammalian , Embryonic Development , Fertilization in Vitro/ethics , Fertilization , Moral Obligations , Personhood , Humans
20.
J Med Ethics ; 39(8): 533-6, 2013 Aug.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23139393

ABSTRACT

The majority of embryos created in natural reproduction die spontaneously within a few weeks of conception. Some have argued that, therefore, if one believes the embryo is a person (in the normative sense) one should find 'natural' reproduction morally problematic. An extension of this argument holds that, if one accepts embryo deaths in natural reproduction, consistency requires that one also accepts embryo deaths that occur in (i) assisted reproduction via in vitro fertilisation (IVF) and (ii) embryo research. In a recent paper in this journal, Timothy Murphy criticises both the initial argument and its extension. Murphy argues that double-effect reasoning can justify embryo deaths both in natural reproduction and IVF, but not in embryo research. Thus, according to Murphy, one can, without being inconsistent, (1) believe the embryo is a person and accept natural reproduction and IVF, and (2) accept natural reproduction and IVF, while rejecting embryo research on the ground that it involves embryo deaths. I show that Murphy's argument is problematic because double effect cannot justify embryo deaths in standard IVF practices. The problem is that the proportionality criterion of double effect is not met by such practices. Thus, Murphy's argument fails to support (1) and (2). An implication of his argument failing to support (2) is that it does not defeat the position I have defended in the past-that if one accepts standard IVF practices one should also accept embryo research, including research with embryos created solely for that purpose.


Subject(s)
Beginning of Human Life/ethics , Embryo Loss , Embryo Research/ethics , Embryo, Mammalian , Embryonic Development , Fertilization in Vitro/ethics , Fertilization , Moral Obligations , Personhood , Humans
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL