Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 20 de 157
Filter
Add more filters

Publication year range
1.
J Clin Ethics ; 28(4): 279-289, 2017.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-29257763

ABSTRACT

A power of attorney for healthcare (POAHC) form gives designated individuals legal status to make healthcare decisions when patients are unable to convey their decisions to medical staff. Completion of a POAHC form is crucial in the provision of comprehensive healthcare, since it helps to ensure that patients' interests, values, and preferences are represented in decisions about their medical treatment. Because increasing numbers of people suffer from debilitating illness and cognitive deficits, healthcare systems may be called upon to navigate the complexities of patients' care without clear directives from the patients themselves. Hence, the healthcare industry encourages all individuals to complete a POAHC form to ensure that persons who have the patients' trust are able to act as their surrogate decision makers. However, sometimes POAHC agents, even when they are patients' trusted agents, lack the capacity to make fully informed decisions that are in the patients' best interests. We describe designated surrogate decision makers who have impaired or diminished judgment capacity as incapacitated surrogates. Decision making that is obviously flawed or questionable is a significant impediment to providing timely and appropriate care to patients. Moreover, failure to redress these issues in a timely and efficient manner can result in significant costs to an institution and a diminished quality of patient care. The authors offer a legal, ethical, and interdisciplinary framework to help navigate cases of incapacitated surrogates.


Subject(s)
Advance Directives/ethics , Decision Making/ethics , Hospitalization , Proxy , Chronic Disease , Humans , Mental Competency , Patient Care Planning/ethics
2.
J Intensive Care Med ; 31(7): 442-50, 2016 Aug.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25990272

ABSTRACT

A major challenge in the era of shared medical decision making is the navigation of complex relationships between the physicians, patients, and surrogates who guide treatment plans for critically ill patients. This review of ethical issues in adult surgical critical care explores factors influencing interactions among the characters most prominently involved in health care decisions in the surgical intensive care unit: the patient, the surrogate, the surgeon, and the intensivist. Ethical tensions in the surgeon-patient relationship in the elective setting may arise from the preoperative surgical covenant and the development of surgical complications. Unlike that of the surgeon, the intensivist's relationship with the individual patient must be balanced with the need to serve other acutely ill patients. Due to their unique perspectives, surgeons and intensivists may disagree about decisions to pursue life-sustaining therapies for critically ill postoperative patients. Finally, although surrogates are asked to make decisions for patients on the basis of the substituted judgment or best interest standards, these models may underestimate the nuances of postoperative surrogate decision making. Strategies to minimize conflicts regarding treatment decisions are centered on early, honest, and consistent communication between all parties.


Subject(s)
Clinical Decision-Making/ethics , Critical Care/ethics , Critical Illness/therapy , Intensive Care Units , Interpersonal Relations , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Physician-Patient Relations/ethics , Surgical Procedures, Operative/ethics , Attitude of Health Personnel , Communication , Critical Illness/psychology , Family/psychology , Humans , Stress, Psychological/psychology , Third-Party Consent/ethics
3.
Gesundheitswesen ; 78(2): 71-5, 2016 Feb.
Article in German | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-26906530

ABSTRACT

An obligation to be healthy in the sauce of a categorical imperative "You shall change your life!" (P. Sloterdijk) does not exist. There is however a moral responsibility to shape ones own life in such a way that the resulting potentials for development can be realized within one owns possibilities (I. Kant). The example of predictive medicine illustrates, why the right not to know can be a responsible way of self governance when dealing with the knowledge of modern biomedicine. This allows the setting of limits within prevention, which preserve the quality of life of the exposed as well as enabling the individual the "acceptance of self" (R. Guardini).


Subject(s)
Ethics, Medical , Health Promotion/ethics , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Physician-Patient Relations/ethics , Preventive Medicine/ethics , Social Responsibility , Germany , Physician's Role , Preventive Health Services/ethics
4.
Prax Kinderpsychol Kinderpsychiatr ; 65(10): 707-728, 2016 Dec.
Article in German | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27923340

ABSTRACT

Decision Support for the Therapy Planning for Young Refugees and Asylum-Seekers with Posttraumatic Disorders Due to the Convention on the Rights of the Child and § 6 of the Asylum Seekers' Benefit Act, there are legal and ethical obligations for the care of minor refugees suffering from trauma-related disorders. In Germany, psychotherapeutic care of adolescent refugees is provided by specialized treatment centers and Child and Adolescent psychiatries with specialized consultation-hours for refugees. Treatment of minor refugees is impeded by various legal and organizational barriers. Many therapists have reservations and uncertainties regarding an appropriate therapy for refugees due to a lack of experience. This means that only a fraction of the young refugees with trauma-related disorders find an ambulatory therapist. In a review of international literature, empirical findings on (interpreter-aided) diagnostics and therapy of young refugees were presented. Practical experiences on therapeutic work with traumatized young refugees were summarized in a decision tree for therapy planning in the ambulatory setting. The decision tree was developed to support therapists in private practices by structuring the therapy process.


Subject(s)
Decision Support Techniques , Patient Care Planning/organization & administration , Refugees/psychology , Stress Disorders, Post-Traumatic/therapy , Adolescent , Ambulatory Care/ethics , Ambulatory Care/legislation & jurisprudence , Attitude of Health Personnel , Child , Decision Trees , Ethics, Medical , Germany , Humans , National Health Programs/ethics , National Health Programs/legislation & jurisprudence , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Patient Care Planning/legislation & jurisprudence , Psychotherapy/ethics , Psychotherapy/legislation & jurisprudence , Psychotherapy/organization & administration , Referral and Consultation/ethics , Referral and Consultation/legislation & jurisprudence , Referral and Consultation/organization & administration , Refugees/legislation & jurisprudence , Stress Disorders, Post-Traumatic/diagnosis , Stress Disorders, Post-Traumatic/psychology
5.
Bioethics ; 29(8): 536-42, 2015 Oct.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25689627

ABSTRACT

Palliative care serves both as an integrated part of treatment and as a last effort to care for those we cannot cure. The extent to which palliative care should be provided and our reasons for doing so have been curiously overlooked in the debate about distributive justice in health and healthcare. We argue that one prominent approach, the Rawlsian approach developed by Norman Daniels, is unable to provide such reasons and such care. This is because of a central feature in Daniels' account, namely that care should be provided to restore people's opportunities. Daniels' view is both unable to provide pain relief to those who need it as a supplement to treatment and, without justice-based reasons to provide palliative care to those whose opportunities cannot be restored. We conclude that this makes Daniels' framework much less attractive.


Subject(s)
Clinical Decision-Making/ethics , Health Care Rationing/ethics , Pain Management/ethics , Palliative Care/ethics , Patient Advocacy , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Patient Rights/ethics , Social Justice/ethics , Terminally Ill , Therapeutics/ethics , Charities/statistics & numerical data , Choice Behavior/ethics , Humans , Pain/etiology , Patient Advocacy/ethics , Stress, Psychological/prevention & control , Terminally Ill/psychology , Therapeutics/adverse effects
6.
Can Fam Physician ; 61(4): 330-4, 2015 Apr.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25873700

ABSTRACT

OBJECTIVE: To review the issues with setting goals of care for patients with advanced dementia, describe the respective roles of the physician and the patient's family in the decision-making process, and suggest ways to support families who need more information about the care options. SOURCES OF INFORMATION: Ovid MEDLINE was searched for relevant articles that were published before March 7, 2014. There were no level I studies identified; most articles provided level III evidence. MAIN MESSAGE: For patients with advanced dementia, their families have an important role in medical decision making. Families should receive timely information about the course of dementia and the care options. They need to understand that a palliative approach to care might be appropriate and does not mean abandonment of the patient. They might also want clarification about their role in the decision-making process, especially if withholding or withdrawing life-prolonging measures are considered. CONCLUSION: Physicians should consider advanced dementia as a terminal disease for which there is a continuum of care that goes from palliative care with life-extending measures to symptomatic interventions only. Clarification of goals of care and family education are of paramount importance to avoid unwanted and burdensome interventions.


Subject(s)
Decision Making , Dementia/nursing , Palliative Care/methods , Physician-Patient Relations , Professional-Family Relations , Terminal Care/methods , Aged, 80 and over , Dementia/psychology , Family/psychology , Female , Humans , Palliative Care/ethics , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Terminal Care/ethics
7.
J Med Philos ; 40(5): 554-83, 2015 Oct.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-26232595

ABSTRACT

In this essay I examine the formal structure of the concept of futility, enabling identification of the appropriate roles played by patient, professional, and society. I argue that the concept of futility does not justify unilateral decisions to forego life-sustaining medical treatment over patient or legitimate surrogate objection, even when futility is determined by a process or subject to ethics committee review. Furthermore, I argue for a limited positive ethical obligation on the part of health care professionals to assist patients in achieving certain restricted goals, including the preservation of life, even in circumstances in which most would agree that that life is of no benefit to the patient. Finally, I address the objection that professional integrity overrides this limited obligation and find the objection unconvincing. In short, my aim in this essay is to see the concept of futility finally buried, once and for all.


Subject(s)
Ethics , Medical Futility/ethics , Withholding Treatment/ethics , Ethics, Medical , Humans , Morals , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Philosophy, Medical
8.
Nurs Ethics ; 22(3): 341-51, 2015 May.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24934270

ABSTRACT

BACKGROUND: According to Norwegian law, nurses are obligated to provide an acceptable level of health assistance to patients and their family members and to allow patients and their family members to participate in the planning of patient care and treatment. AIM: The aim of this study is to compare the perceptions of older patients undergoing haemodialysis treatment and of their next of kin and of nurses regarding patient participation in the context of haemodialysis treatment. RESEARCH DESIGN: The study adopts an approach that is both comparative and explorative in nature by examining the narratives of patients, nurses and next of kin and by performing critical discourse analysis as outlined by Fairclough. ETHICAL CONSIDERATIONS: Permission to carry out the research was granted by the Regional Committee for Medical and Health Research Ethics of Mid-Norway and by the participating hospitals. Informed consent and confidentiality were ensured. FINDINGS: Two discourses were found: (a) the discourse of paternalism with the discursive practices of achieving physiological balance in patients, trusting the healthcare team and being excluded or included in the difficult end-of-life decision-making process, and (b) the discourse of patient participation, with the themes of maintaining patients' quality of life and trusting patients. CONCLUSION: The participation of older patients and their next of kin was not as well integrated as social practice in dialysis units. The dominant discourse seemed to have an ideology and social practice of paternalism. However, there existed hegemonic struggles for an ideology of patient participation that involved (a) achieving physiological balance in patients versus maintaining patients' quality of life, (b) trusting the healthcare team versus trusting the patient, and (c) being excluded versus included in the difficult end-of-life decision-making process.


Subject(s)
Attitude of Health Personnel , Decision Making/ethics , Hemodialysis Units, Hospital/standards , Patient Participation/methods , Perception , Hemodialysis Units, Hospital/ethics , Humans , Norway , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Quality of Life
9.
World J Surg ; 38(7): 1631-7, 2014 Jul.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24849199

ABSTRACT

Futility has been a contentious topic in medicine for several decades. Surgery in critical or end-of-life situations often raises difficult questions about futility. In this article, we discuss the definition of futility, methods for resolving futility disputes, and some ways to reframe the futility debate to a more fruitful discussion about the goals of care, better communication between surgeon and patient/surrogate, and palliative surgical care. Many definitions of futile therapy have been discussed. The most controversial of these is "qualitative futility" which describes a situation in which the treatment provided is likely to result in an unacceptable quality of life. This is an area of continued controversy because it has been impossible to identify universally held beliefs about acceptable quality of life. Many authors have described methods for resolving futility disputes, including community standards and legalistic multi-step due process protocols. Others, however, have abandoned the concept of futility altogether as an unhelpful term. Reframing the issue of futility as one of inadequate physician-patient communication, these authors have advocated for methods of improving communication and strengthening the patient-physician relationship. Finally, we discuss the utilization of consultants who may be of use in resolving futility disputes: ethics committees, palliative care specialists, pastoral care teams, and dedicated patient advocates. Involving these specialists in a futility conflict can help improve communication and provide invaluable assistance in arriving at the appropriate treatment decision.


Subject(s)
Dissent and Disputes , Medical Futility/ethics , Palliative Care , Surgical Procedures, Operative/ethics , Communication , Ethics Committees , Humans , Negotiating , Patient Advocacy , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Patient Preference , Physician-Patient Relations , Quality of Life
10.
Unfallchirurg ; 117(5): 399-405, 2014 May.
Article in German | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24831869

ABSTRACT

We report on a 32-year-old patient, who developed septic shock, toxic shock-like syndrome, and multiple organ failure following nectrotizing fasciitis. Amputations had to be performed on all extremities. Subsequently, she developed secondary sclerosing cholangitis. Treatment goals had to be reassessed, since long-term survival seemed doubtful and, in the best case, burdened with severe handicap. We discuss the evaluation of the treatment goals, utilizing a structured model of goal-setting. In the first step the treatment goal is identified based on the patient's wishes. This goal's realistic achievability is verified considering scientific evidence and medical experience. The benefit of the aspired goal is set in relation to risks and burden of the necessary treatment measures in a third step. The resulting benefit-risk ratio must be evaluated by the patient or her representative. Treatment goals have to be reevaluated if the assessment of achievability or the benefit-risk ratio are disadvantageous. In this case, the initial therapeutic goal was retained. After an extraordinarily prolonged and complex therapy including reconstructive surgery the patient is now living independently at home.


Subject(s)
Amputation, Surgical/ethics , Critical Illness/therapy , Decision Making/ethics , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Physician-Patient Relations/ethics , Surgical Procedures, Operative/ethics , Traumatology/ethics , Adult , Decision Support Techniques , Female , Germany , Humans , Patient-Centered Care/ethics
11.
Crim Behav Ment Health ; 23(4): 304-14, 2013 Oct.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24101410

ABSTRACT

ARGUMENT: Forensic case formulation, of increasing interest to practitioners and researchers raises many ethical, theoretical and practical issues for them. CONCLUSION: Systemic, contextual and individual factors which need to be considered include the multitude of staff often involved with any one individual, the pressure to 'get it right' because of the range of risk implications that are associated with individuals within forensic mental health settings, and individual parameters, for example reluctance to be engaged with services.


Subject(s)
Criminals/psychology , Mental Disorders/therapy , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Clinical Competence , Humans , Informed Consent , Mental Disorders/diagnosis , Patient Care Team/ethics
12.
Issues Ment Health Nurs ; 34(9): 639-47, 2013 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24004357

ABSTRACT

Despite growing awareness and evidence linking childhood sexual abuse (CSA) to numerous ongoing health problems in adulthood, the integration of this knowledge into nursing practice remains inconsistent. This article reports the results of a study that explored nurses' perspectives on, and experiences with, providing care for adults with mental health problems who may also have histories of CSA. Nurses' views underscore the challenges and complexities involved when providing care for this population. The themes of nurses' knowledge and comfort levels, ethical practice, patient care considerations, and system issues are used to discuss nurses' understandings, perspectives, and experiences.


Subject(s)
Adult Survivors of Child Abuse/psychology , Attitude of Health Personnel , Child Abuse, Sexual/psychology , Mental Disorders/nursing , Mental Disorders/psychology , Nurse's Role/psychology , Adult , Child , Child Abuse, Sexual/diagnosis , Child Abuse, Sexual/ethics , Ethics, Nursing , Female , Humans , Interview, Psychological , Male , Manitoba , Nursing Diagnosis , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Psychotic Disorders/nursing , Psychotic Disorders/psychology , Stress Disorders, Post-Traumatic/nursing , Stress Disorders, Post-Traumatic/psychology , Surveys and Questionnaires , Tertiary Care Centers
13.
Ann Emerg Med ; 60(4): 485-91, 2012 Oct.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22699019

ABSTRACT

The expanding role of emergency medicine in the care of potential organ donors presents unique ethical challenges. This article introduces emergency providers to the ethical challenges of organ donation, including issues of patient autonomy and consent, public perception and trust, goals of care, and the determination of death.


Subject(s)
Emergency Service, Hospital/ethics , Tissue Donors/ethics , Death , Family , Humans , Informed Consent/ethics , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Personal Autonomy , Tissue and Organ Procurement/ethics , Trust
14.
J Med Ethics ; 38(11): 664-8, 2012 Nov.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22811556

ABSTRACT

The main premise of the Royal Dutch Medical Association's (RDMA) guideline on palliative sedation is that palliative sedation, contrary to euthanasia, is normal medical practice. Although we do not deny the ethical distinctions between euthanasia and palliative sedation, we will critically analyse the guideline's argumentation strategy with which euthanasia is demarcated from palliative sedation. First, we will analyse the guideline's main premise, which entails that palliative sedation is normal medical treatment. After this, we will critically discuss three crucial propositions of the guideline that are used to support this premise: (1) the patient's life expectancy should not exceed 2 weeks; (2) the aim of the physician should be to relieve suffering and (3) expert consultation is optional. We will conclude that, if inherent problematic aspects of palliative sedation are taken seriously, palliative sedation is less normal than it is now depicted in the guideline.


Subject(s)
Deep Sedation/ethics , Double Effect Principle , Palliative Care/ethics , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Practice Guidelines as Topic , Practice Patterns, Physicians'/ethics , Stress, Psychological/prevention & control , Terminal Care/ethics , Analgesics, Opioid/administration & dosage , Conscious Sedation/ethics , Consciousness/drug effects , Ethical Analysis , Euthanasia, Passive/ethics , Humans , Intention , Life Expectancy , Netherlands , Patient Care Planning/standards , Patient Care Planning/trends , Practice Guidelines as Topic/standards , Practice Patterns, Physicians'/standards , Practice Patterns, Physicians'/trends , Referral and Consultation , Societies, Medical , Time Factors
15.
J Med Ethics ; 38(11): 647-51, 2012 Nov.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22692859

ABSTRACT

Contrary to the widespread concern about over-treatment at the end of life, today, patient preferences for palliative care at the end of life are frequently respected. However, ethically challenging situations in the current healthcare climate are, instead, situations in which a competent patient requests active treatment with the goal of life-prolongation while the physician suggests best supportive care only. The argument of futility has often been used to justify unilateral decisions made by physicians to withhold or withdraw life-sustaining treatment. However, we argue that neither the concept of futility nor that of patient autonomy alone is apt for resolving situations in which physicians are confronted with patients' requests for active treatment. Instead, we integrate the relevant arguments that have been put forward in the academic discussion about 'futile' treatment into an ethical algorithm with five guiding questions: (1) Is there a chance that medical intervention will be effective in achieving the patient's treatment goal? (2) How does the physician evaluate the expected benefit and the potential harm of the treatment? (3) Does the patient understand his or her medical situation? (4) Does the patient prefer receiving treatment after evaluating the benefit-harm ratio and the costs? (5) Does the treatment require many resources? This algorithm shall facilitate approaching patients' requests for treatments deemed futile by the physician in a systematic way, and responding to these requests in an ethically appropriate manner. It thereby adds substantive considerations to the current procedural approaches of conflict resolution in order to improve decision making among physicians, patients and families.


Subject(s)
Checklist , Decision Making/ethics , Life Expectancy , Medical Futility , Palliative Care , Patient Care Planning , Patients , Physicians/ethics , Practice Patterns, Physicians'/ethics , Withholding Treatment , Algorithms , Choice Behavior/ethics , Dissent and Disputes , Ethics, Medical , Humans , Palliative Care/economics , Palliative Care/ethics , Palliative Care/trends , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Patient Care Planning/standards , Patient Care Planning/trends , Personal Autonomy , Physician-Patient Relations/ethics , Practice Patterns, Physicians'/economics , Practice Patterns, Physicians'/standards , Practice Patterns, Physicians'/trends , Terminal Care/ethics , Terminal Care/standards , Terminal Care/trends , Treatment Outcome , Withholding Treatment/economics , Withholding Treatment/ethics , Withholding Treatment/trends
16.
J Med Ethics ; 38(11): 672-6, 2012 Nov.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22562947

ABSTRACT

A paediatric clinical trial conducted in a developing country is likely to encounter conditions or illnesses in participants unrelated to the study. Since local healthcare resources may be inadequate to meet these needs, research clinicians may face the dilemma of deciding when to provide ancillary care and to what extent. The authors propose a model for identifying ancillary care obligations that draws on assessments of urgency, the capacity of the local healthcare infrastructure and the capacity of the research infrastructure. The model lends itself to a decision tree that can be adapted to the local context and resources so as to provide procedural guidance. This approach can help in planning and establishing organisational policies that govern the provision of ancillary care.


Subject(s)
Clinical Trials as Topic/ethics , Delivery of Health Care/ethics , Developing Countries , Health Care Rationing/ethics , Health Resources , Health Services Accessibility/ethics , Moral Obligations , Patient Care Planning , Research Personnel/ethics , Researcher-Subject Relations/ethics , Decision Trees , Delivery of Health Care/methods , Delivery of Health Care/standards , Ethics, Research , Health Services Accessibility/economics , Health Services Accessibility/standards , Health Services Needs and Demand/economics , Health Services Needs and Demand/ethics , Humans , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Patient Care Planning/standards , Research Subjects
18.
Dent Update ; 39(5): 313-6, 318-20, 323-4 passim, 2012 Jun.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22852509

ABSTRACT

UNLABELLED: Prior to undertaking any elective,'cosmetic' dental procedures, it is vital for the treating dentist to discuss the merits and drawbacks of all viable options. It is important that the patient understands what the consequences and limitations of treatment are likely to be, and what the potential failures could entail later in his/her life. Informed consent should be obtained (preferably in writing) and the clinical notes and records should be clearly documented, with accurate and concise details provided of all the investigations carried out, and their findings, as well as including details of the various discussions that have taken place. Dentists need to be aware of the existence of heightened expectations in this group of patients and be cautious about accepting patients who have unrealistic 'cosmetic' expectations. Where possible, cosmetic or aesthetic dental treatment should be provided which is minimally destructive and, in the long-term, be in the 'best interests' of the patient. Important matters such as the gaining of informed consent and maintaining meticulous, contemporaneous dental records will also be emphasized. It is hoped that the article will provide clear definitions of some commonly used terms such as 'ethical marketing', 'ethics', and 'values', which are often used in association with the marketing, planning and undertaking of supposedly 'cosmetic' dental procedures. The important role of less invasive alternative treatment options will also be emphasized. CLINICAL RELEVANCE: The aims of this article are to consider the common pitfalls that may arise when contemplating the marketing and provision of invasive,'cosmetic, dental restorations and to discuss how best to avoid a dento-legal claim where such treatment plans may not fulfil the patient's desired outcome.


Subject(s)
Dentist-Patient Relations/ethics , Esthetics, Dental , Ethics, Dental , Marketing of Health Services/ethics , Advertising/ethics , Attitude to Health , Beauty Culture/ethics , Dental Care/ethics , Dental Prosthesis/ethics , Dental Records , Dental Veneers/ethics , Female , Humans , Informed Consent/ethics , Male , Minimally Invasive Surgical Procedures/ethics , Motivation , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Risk Assessment/ethics , Tooth Bleaching/ethics , Tooth Preparation/ethics
20.
J Am Coll Dent ; 79(4): 56-63, 2012.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23654165

ABSTRACT

In this case a young dentist has signed onto a managed care plan that has several attractive features. Eventually, however, he notices that he makes little or no net revenue for some of the work that he does. A colleague recommends that he use different labs for different patients, with labs matched to each patient's dental plan and coverage. Offshore labs are used for managed care patients. Three knowledgeable experts comment on the case, two with many years of private practice experience, two who are dental educators holding master's degrees in philosophy and bioethics.


Subject(s)
Dental Care/ethics , Dentists/ethics , Ethics, Dental , Laboratories, Dental/ethics , Conflict of Interest , Cost Control/economics , Cost Control/ethics , Dental Care/economics , Dental Technicians/ethics , Dentist-Patient Relations/ethics , Dentists/economics , Fees, Dental/ethics , Financial Management/economics , Financial Management/ethics , Humans , Interprofessional Relations/ethics , Laboratories, Dental/economics , Managed Care Programs/economics , Managed Care Programs/ethics , Patient Care Planning/economics , Patient Care Planning/ethics , Practice Management, Dental/economics , Practice Management, Dental/ethics
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL