Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Mostrar: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 20 de 378
Filtrar
7.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 51(2): 16-21, 2021 Mar.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33840101

RESUMEN

Harrowing stories reported in the media describe Covid-19 ravaging through families. This essay reports professional experiences of this phenomenon, family clustering, as encountered during the pandemic's spread across Southern California. We identify three ethical challenges following from it: Family clustering impedes shared decision-making by reducing available surrogate decision-makers for incapacitated patients, increases the emotional burdens of surrogate decision-makers, and exacerbates health disparities for and the suffering of people of color at increased likelihood of experiencing family clustering. We propose that, in response to these challenges, efforts in advance care planning be expanded, emotional support offered to surrogates and family members be increased, more robust state guidance be issued on ethical decision-making for unrepresented patients, ethics consultation be increased in the setting of conflict following from family clustering dynamics, and health care professionals pay more attention to systemic and personal racial biases and inequities that affect patient care and the surrogate experience.


Asunto(s)
Planificación Anticipada de Atención , COVID-19/epidemiología , Salud de la Familia , Familia/psicología , Salud de las Minorías , Atención al Paciente , Planificación Anticipada de Atención/ética , Planificación Anticipada de Atención/legislación & jurisprudencia , California/epidemiología , Análisis por Conglomerados , Toma de Decisiones Conjunta , Salud de la Familia/ética , Salud de la Familia/etnología , Disparidades en el Estado de Salud , Humanos , Salud de las Minorías/ética , Salud de las Minorías/etnología , Atención al Paciente/ética , Atención al Paciente/psicología , SARS-CoV-2 , Apoyo Social , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética
8.
Arch Dis Child Fetal Neonatal Ed ; 106(3): 258-264, 2021 May.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33127737

RESUMEN

OBJECTIVE: To evaluate the opinions of parents of newborns following their infant's enrolment into a neonatal research study through the process of deferred consent. DESIGN: Mixed-methods, observational study, interviewing 100 parents recently approached for deferred consent. SETTING: Tertiary-level neonatal intensive care unit, Melbourne, Australia. RESULTS: All 100 parents interviewed had consented to the study/studies using deferred consent; 62% had also experienced a prospective neonatal consent process. Eighty-nine per cent were 'satisfied' with the deferred consent process. The most common reason given for consenting was 'to help future babies'. Negative comments regarding deferred consent mostly related to the timing of the consent approach, and some related to a perceived loss of parental rights. A deferred approach was preferred by 51%, 24% preferred a prospective approach and 25% were unsure. Those who thought prospective consent would not have been preferable cited impaired decision-making, inappropriate timing of an approach before birth and their preference for removal of the decision-making burden via deferred consent. Seventy-seven per cent thought they would have given the same response if approached prospectively; those who would have declined reported that a prospective approach under stressful conditions was unwelcome and too overwhelming. CONCLUSION: In our sample, 89% of parents of infants enrolled in neonatal research using deferred consent considered it acceptable and half would not have preferred prospective consent. The ability to make a more considered decision under less stressful circumstances was key to the acceptability of deferred consent.


Asunto(s)
Investigación Biomédica , Formularios de Consentimiento , Investigación sobre Servicios de Salud , Neonatología/métodos , Padres/psicología , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética , Adulto , Australia , Investigación Biomédica/ética , Investigación Biomédica/métodos , Femenino , Investigación sobre Servicios de Salud/ética , Investigación sobre Servicios de Salud/métodos , Humanos , Recién Nacido , Masculino , Selección de Paciente , Investigación Cualitativa , Percepción Social/psicología , Factores de Tiempo
9.
Cuad Bioet ; 31(103): 309-317, 2020.
Artículo en Español | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33375798

RESUMEN

Lately, number of divorces is increasing, nevertheless, a parents' divorce can become a traumatic problem for paediatric patients. Consequently, the aim of this study was to analyze the ethical conflicts that appear in the relationship between physician/parents/son/daughter, and more specifically those that a divorce generates. A descriptive study was developed through a survey composed by 39 items. Previously, an exhaustive bibliographic analysis was carried out. Our results show that only 35% of paediatricians interviewed have been educated in bioethics although this issue is important in daily practice. Other items show that 57,5% would not cancel a pharmacological treatment in order to improve quality of life. Also, they would react against a wrong parents' decision (82,5%). They give low value to the minor`s decision (6,05%), and rarely inform exclusively to adolescents (5%). In contrast, paediatricians sometimes ask to adolescents (20%) in first place and involved them to decide in 90% of cases. Besides, there are differences in the relation with fathers and mothers, 17,5% of mothers are informed exclusively, a fact that never happens with fathers. Ethics has an intrinsic value very important in daily clinical decisions in order to respect the rules and to adapt them to the situation of every paediatric patient. When an important ethical conflict become, as a divorce is, it is essential to know who must be informed and the rights everyone has to make a decision. It is complicated to the paediatricians yet to develop 41/2002 law for Patient's autonomy.


Asunto(s)
Divorcio/ética , Negociación , Adolescente , Factores de Edad , Bioética/educación , Niño , Custodia del Niño/ética , Derechos Civiles , Toma de Decisiones Clínicas , Divorcio/legislación & jurisprudencia , Educación Médica , Padre , Femenino , Humanos , Consentimiento Informado , Masculino , Madres , Pediatras/educación , Rol del Médico , Relaciones Profesional-Familia , Psicología del Adolescente , Psicología Infantil , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética , Consentimiento por Terceros/legislación & jurisprudencia , Revelación de la Verdad/ética
10.
Pediatrics ; 146(5)2020 11.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33028661

RESUMEN

The current coronavirus disease 2019 (COVID-19) pandemic has triggered an intense global research effort to inform the life-saving work of frontline clinicians who need reliable information as soon as possible. Yet research done in pressured circumstances can lead to ethical dilemmas, especially for vulnerable research subjects. We present the case of a child with neurocognitive impairment who is diagnosed with COVID-19 infection after presenting with fever and a seizure. The child lives in a group home and is in the custody of the state; her parents lost parental rights many years ago. Some members of the health care team want to enroll her in a randomized clinical trial evaluating an experimental treatment of COVID-19. For minor patients to enroll in this clinical trial, the institutional review board requires assent of patients and consent of guardians. An ethics consult is called to help identify relevant concerns in enrollment. In the accompanying case discussion, we address historical perspectives on research involving people with disabilities; proper management of research participation for people with disabilities including consent by proxy, therapeutic misconception, and other threats to the ethical validity of clinical trials; and the potentially conflicting obligations of researchers and clinicians.


Asunto(s)
Antivirales/uso terapéutico , Betacoronavirus , Infecciones por Coronavirus/tratamiento farmacológico , Competencia Mental , Trastornos Neurocognitivos/complicaciones , Neumonía Viral/tratamiento farmacológico , Ensayos Clínicos Controlados Aleatorios como Asunto/ética , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética , COVID-19 , Niño , Infecciones por Coronavirus/complicaciones , Femenino , Humanos , Pandemias , Neumonía Viral/complicaciones , SARS-CoV-2
11.
Am J Public Health ; 110(12): 1786-1789, 2020 12.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33058705

RESUMEN

Unaccompanied migrant children seeking asylum status in the United States are often forced to undergo dental radiographs, or x-rays, to verify that they are younger than 18 years.The application of third molar dental radiographs is methodologically flawed and should not be employed as a determinant of chronological age. Furthermore, the use of such tests without obtaining informed consent from either the youth or an objective advocate is unethical.Finally, the legal and health consequences of these inappropriately applied tests are severe and jeopardize the safety and security of these vulnerable minors.


Asunto(s)
Determinación de la Edad por los Dientes/métodos , Radiografía Dental/ética , Refugiados , Adolescente , Niño , Humanos , Tercer Molar/diagnóstico por imagen , Radiografía Dental/efectos adversos , Radiografía Dental/métodos , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética
12.
Am J Bioeth ; 20(6): 4-16, 2020 06.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32441596

RESUMEN

The past decade has witnessed escalating legal and ethical challenges to the diagnosis of death by neurologic criteria (DNC). The legal tactic of demanding consent for the apnea test, if successful, can halt the DNC. However, US law is currently unsettled and inconsistent in this matter. Consent has been required in several trial cases in Montana and Kansas but not in Virginia and Nevada. In this paper, we analyze and evaluate the legal and ethical bases for requiring consent before apnea testing and defend such a requirement by appealing to ethical and legal principles of informed consent and battery and the right to refuse medical treatment. We conclude by considering and rebutting two major objections to a consent requirement for apnea testing: (1) a justice-based objection to allocate scarce resources fairly and (2) a social utility objection that halting the diagnosis of brain death will reduce the number of organ donors.


Asunto(s)
Apnea/diagnóstico , Muerte Encefálica/diagnóstico , Muerte Encefálica/legislación & jurisprudencia , Técnicas de Diagnóstico Neurológico/ética , Técnicas de Diagnóstico del Sistema Respiratorio/ética , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética , Consentimiento por Terceros/legislación & jurisprudencia , Humanos , Jurisprudencia , Estados Unidos/epidemiología
13.
Am J Bioeth ; 20(2): 44-48, 2020 Feb.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31990251

RESUMEN

Incapacitated adult patients are commonly divided into two groups for purposes of decision making; those with a surrogate and those without. Respectively, these groups are often referred to as represented and unrepresented, and the relative ethics of decision making between them raises two particular issues. The first issue involves the differential application of the best interests standard between groups. Second is the prevailing notion that representedness and unrepresentedness are categorical phenomena, though it is more aptly understood as a multidimensional and continuous variable based on relational moral authority. This paper examines the nature of representedness as it relates to ethical norms of surrogate decision making.


Asunto(s)
Toma de Decisiones/ética , Defensa del Paciente/clasificación , Defensa del Paciente/normas , Apoderado , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética , Adulto , Anciano , Humanos , Principios Morales , Normas Sociales
15.
Bioethics ; 34(3): 272-280, 2020 03.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31598984

RESUMEN

The wishes of registered organ donors are regularly set aside when family members object to donation. This genuine overruling of the wishes of the deceased raises difficult ethical questions. A successful argument for providing the family with a veto must (a) provide reason to disregard the wishes of the dead, and (b) establish why the family should be allowed to decide. One branch of justification seeks to reconcile the family veto with important ideas about respecting property rights, preserving autonomy, and preventing harm. These arguments are ultimately unsuccessful. Another branch of arguments is consequentialist, pointing out the negative consequences of removing the veto. Whether construed as concerning family distress or as a potential drop in the organs available, these arguments are unsuccessful; the first fails to recognize the tremendous distress associated with waiting for an organ, while the second has little supporting evidence. A final section considers and rejects whether combining some of the arguments just examined could justify the family veto. We should thus remove the family veto in organ donation.


Asunto(s)
Toma de Decisiones/ética , Análisis Ético , Conflicto Familiar/psicología , Apoderado/psicología , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética , Donantes de Tejidos/psicología , Obtención de Tejidos y Órganos/ética , Humanos
16.
J Med Ethics ; 45(11): 751-754, 2019 11.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31506293

RESUMEN

The shortage of organs for transplantation by its nature prompts ethical dilemmas. For example, although there is an imperative to save human life and reduce suffering by maximising the supply of vital organs, there is an equally important obligation to ensure that the process by which we increase the supply respects the rights of all stakeholders. In a relatively unexamined practice in the USA, organs are procured from unrepresented decedents without their express consent. Unrepresented decedents have no known healthcare wishes or advance care planning document; they also lack a surrogate. The Revised Uniform Anatomical Gift Act (RUAGA) of 2006 sends a mixed message about the procurement of organs from this patient population and there are hospitals that authorise donation. In addition, in adopting the RUAGA, some states included provisions that clearly allow organ procurement from unrepresented decedents. An important unanswered question is whether this practice meets the canons of ethical permissibility. The current Brief Report presents two principled approaches to the topic as a way of highlighting some of the complexities involved. Concluding remarks offer suggestions for future research and discussion.


Asunto(s)
Obtención de Tejidos y Órganos/ética , Obtención de Tejidos y Órganos/métodos , Humanos , Consentimiento Informado/ética , Consentimiento Informado/legislación & jurisprudencia , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética , Consentimiento por Terceros/legislación & jurisprudencia
17.
Narrat Inq Bioeth ; 9(2): 173-177, 2019.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31447455

RESUMEN

A living will is a document in which an individual can communicate his or her health care choices to loved ones in the event that he or she is unable to do so directly. Many surrogate decision-makers use living wills as guides; however, the existence of such documents does not entirely relieve them of their burden. Surrogate decision-makers often need to consider the impact of the personal and family burdens entailed by their decisions, and the stress accompanying these burdens regularly creates high levels of anxiety and depression. This stress can be exacerbated when two surrogate decision-makers are at loggerheads as to the best way forward. This case study illustrates the effects of stress accompanying disagreement among surrogate decision-makers-here, the patient's adult sons-and demonstrates that a process of listening can help the bioethicist identify the values that are important to the patient and, consequently, to the surrogate as well, and use these values to help address the issue.


Asunto(s)
Directivas Anticipadas/ética , Cuidados Críticos/ética , Padre , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética , Anciano , Disentimientos y Disputas , Neoplasias de Cabeza y Cuello/terapia , Humanos , Voluntad en Vida/ética , Masculino , Carcinoma de Células Escamosas de Cabeza y Cuello/terapia
18.
AMA J Ethics ; 21(7): E582-586, 2019 07 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31333173

RESUMEN

Increasingly, clinicians confront patients who are incapacitated and have no available surrogate. Such unrepresented patients cannot consent to proposed health care, and nobody else is available who is authorized to consent on their behalf. Despite the challenge of decision making for unrepresented patients, few laws or professional organization policy statements offer a solution. This article helps fill this void by describing the top 5 things clinicians should know when they are caring for unrepresented patients: (1) realize that these patients are highly vulnerable; (2) confirm that the patient is incapacitated; (3) confirm that the patient is unrepresented; (4) appreciate variability among state law decision-making processes for unrepresented patients; (5) use guardianship only as a last resort.


Asunto(s)
Toma de Decisiones/ética , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética , Consentimiento por Terceros/legislación & jurisprudencia , Poblaciones Vulnerables , Política de Salud/legislación & jurisprudencia , Humanos , Tutores Legales , Formulación de Políticas , Estados Unidos
19.
AMA J Ethics ; 21(7): E587-593, 2019 07 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31333174

RESUMEN

Unrepresented patients are those who have no surrogate or advance directive to guide medical decision making for them when they become incapacitated. While there is no perfect solution to the problem of making medical decisions for such vulnerable patients, 3 different approaches are noted in the literature: a physician approach, an ethics committee approach, and a guardianship approach. Recent policies and laws have required an approach that is "tiered" with respect to both who is involved and the gravity of the medical treatment questions at issue. In a general sense, some variant of a tiered approach is likely the best possible solution for jurisdictions and health institutions-both those already with and those without a tiered approach-to the challenging puzzle of treating unrepresented patients.


Asunto(s)
Toma de Decisiones/ética , Política de Salud/legislación & jurisprudencia , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética , Consentimiento por Terceros/legislación & jurisprudencia , Poblaciones Vulnerables/legislación & jurisprudencia , Directivas Anticipadas , Comités de Ética Clínica/ética , Comités de Ética Clínica/legislación & jurisprudencia , Humanos , Tutores Legales , Médicos/ética , Médicos/legislación & jurisprudencia , Estados Unidos
20.
AMA J Ethics ; 21(7): E611-616, 2019 07 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-31333178

RESUMEN

Unrepresented patients are hospital patients who lack decision-making capacity but have no advance directive and no one to serve as a legally authorized surrogate. An important first step in efforts to change the law and develop organizational policies that help respond to these patients' needs is determining which patients should be considered unrepresented and which aspects of hospital care should receive attention. This article proposes working definitions of unrepresented patient and important medical decisions based on the work of one statewide initiative, the Unrepresented Patients Project for Illinois.


Asunto(s)
Toma de Decisiones/ética , Hospitalización , Pacientes Internos , Defensa del Paciente/legislación & jurisprudencia , Rol del Médico , Consentimiento por Terceros/ética , Consentimiento por Terceros/legislación & jurisprudencia , Humanos , Terminología como Asunto , Estados Unidos
SELECCIÓN DE REFERENCIAS
DETALLE DE LA BÚSQUEDA
...