Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Results 1 - 20 de 38
Filter
3.
Ethics Hum Res ; 45(5): 39-43, 2023.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37777979

ABSTRACT

Generative artificial intelligence (AI) has the potential to transform many aspects of scholarly publishing. Authors, peer reviewers, and editors might use AI in a variety of ways, and those uses might augment their existing work or might instead be intended to replace it. We are editors of bioethics and humanities journals who have been contemplating the implications of this ongoing transformation. We believe that generative AI may pose a threat to the goals that animate our work but could also be valuable for achieving those goals. In the interests of fostering a wider conversation about how generative AI may be used, we have developed a preliminary set of recommendations for its use in scholarly publishing. We hope that the recommendations and rationales set out here will help the scholarly community navigate toward a deeper understanding of the strengths, limits, and challenges of AI for responsible scholarly work.


Subject(s)
Editorial Policies , Publishing , Humans , Scholarly Communication , Artificial Intelligence , Technology
4.
Hastings Cent Rep ; 53(5): 3-6, 2023 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37777997

ABSTRACT

Generative artificial intelligence (AI) has the potential to transform many aspects of scholarly publishing. Authors, peer reviewers, and editors might use AI in a variety of ways, and those uses might augment their existing work or might instead be intended to replace it. We are editors of bioethics and humanities journals who have been contemplating the implications of this ongoing transformation. We believe that generative AI may pose a threat to the goals that animate our work but could also be valuable for achieving those goals. In the interests of fostering a wider conversation about how generative AI may be used, we have developed a preliminary set of recommendations for its use in scholarly publishing. We hope that the recommendations and rationales set out here will help the scholarly community navigate toward a deeper understanding of the strengths, limits, and challenges of AI for responsible scholarly work.


Subject(s)
Bioethics , Publishing , Humans , Editorial Policies , Scholarly Communication , Artificial Intelligence
6.
Med Health Care Philos ; 26(4): 499-503, 2023 Dec.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37863860

ABSTRACT

Generative artificial intelligence (AI) has the potential to transform many aspects of scholarly publishing. Authors, peer reviewers, and editors might use AI in a variety of ways, and those uses might augment their existing work or might instead be intended to replace it. We are editors of bioethics and humanities journals who have been contemplating the implications of this ongoing transformation. We believe that generative AI may pose a threat to the goals that animate our work but could also be valuable for achieving those goals. In the interests of fostering a wider conversation about how generative AI may be used, we have developed a preliminary set of recommendations for its use in scholarly publishing. We hope that the recommendations and rationales set out here will help the scholarly community navigate toward a deeper understanding of the strengths, limits, and challenges of AI for responsible scholarly work.


Subject(s)
Bioethics , Publishing , Humans , Scholarly Communication , Artificial Intelligence
7.
J Med Philos ; 47(2): 240-256, 2022 05 11.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-35543468

ABSTRACT

Brain transplants have long been no more than the subject of science fiction and engaging thought experiments. That is no longer true. Neuroscientists have announced their intention to transplant the head of a volunteer onto a donated body. Response has been decidedly mixed. How should we think about the moral permissibility of head transplants? Is it a life-saving/life-enhancing opportunity that appropriately expands the boundaries of medical practice? Or, is it a bioethical morass that ought not to be attempted? For the purposes of this paper, I set aside questions regarding the surgical operation's technological plausibility so as to focus on very basic questions regarding personal identity and the morality of head transplantation. The analysis begins with an exploration of the embodiment of persons. It considers whether persons can be conceptually distinguished from all parts of their body, even if they cannot be physically separated from some parts without loss of personhood. It argues that in most cases replacing body parts with reasonably similar parts will not destroy the conditions for sustaining personhood. However, as I explore, the phenomenology of personhood is such that some physical changes may prove to be too significant to maintain personal identity successfully over time. Given such complexity and the significance of the costs involved, the moral permissibility of head transplantation likely depends on recognizing that persons may give permission to collaborate in common activities, including projects with which others deeply disagree, provided that they only utilize the services and resources of free and consenting others.


Subject(s)
Personhood , Self Concept , Brain , Humans , Morals
8.
HEC Forum ; 34(2): 103-114, 2022 Jun.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-35604507

ABSTRACT

Bioethicists often remind health care professionals to pay close attention to issues of diversity and inclusion. Approaches to ethics consultation, where the perspective of the bioethicist is taken to be more morally correct or necessarily authoritative, have been critiqued as inappropriately authoritarian. Despite such apparent recognition of the importance of respecting moral diversity and the inclusion of different viewpoints, authoritarianism is all too often the approach adopted, especially as bioethics has shifted evermore into concerns for public policy. Yet, secular values and philosophical principles are not morally neutral; nor are the private moral convictions of bioethicists. Such analysis is always grounded in particular understandings of the right and the good, the virtuous and the just. Critical examination of common treatments and new alternatives is essential for the careful scientific practice of medicine. The same is true with regard to bioethics. Stagnating in customary or accepted claims of a common secular morality or a standard set of bioethical principles out of an unwillingness to explore the real diversity of moral thought, including traditional religious and cultural worldviews, fails to tap the human capacity to find innovative solutions to the complex challenges facing medicine.


Subject(s)
Bioethics , Ethics Consultation , Cultural Diversity , Ethicists , Humans , Morals
9.
Am J Bioeth ; 21(6): 22-25, 2021 06.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34036878
10.
HEC Forum ; 32(3): 191-197, 2020 Sep.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32737622

ABSTRACT

The day-to-day work of clinical ethics consultants and healthcare ethics committees can easily become overly routine. Too much routine, however, comes with a risk that morally important practices will be reduced to mere bureaucratic formalities, while practitioners become desensitized to ethically significant distinctions between cases. Clinical ethics consultation and organizational ethics must be set within the broader social and cultural context of the healthcare environment. This practice requires looking beyond mere legal compliance and the routinely false assumption that there are unambiguous ethical norms that easily govern clinical ethics and hospital policy formation. Together the essays in this issue of HEC Forum challenge readers to rethink taken-for-granted assumptions regarding patient care, physician obligation, clinical ethics consultation, and organizational ethics.


Subject(s)
Ethics Consultation/trends , Ethics, Institutional , Ethics, Medical , Ethics Consultation/standards , Humans
11.
J Med Philos ; 44(5): 603-620, 2019 09 17.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32479622

ABSTRACT

Organ procurement policy from the recently deceased recasts families into gatekeepers of a scarce medical resource. To the frustration of organ procurement teams, families do not always authorize organ donation. As a result, efforts to increase the number of organs available for transplantation often seek to limit the authority of families to refuse organ retrieval. For example, in some locales if a deceased family member has satisfied the legal conditions for first-person prior assent, a much looser and easier standard to satisfy than informed consent, organ retrieval may proceed despite the family's objections. Some countries have replaced voluntary consent to organ donation with forms of organ conscription. Often referred to under the misnomer "presumed consent," such policies legalize the harvesting of organs at death, unless individuals exercise official options to opt out. As this article explores, however, there are good grounds for affirming the authority of the family to consent to or to deny organ donation on behalf of recently deceased family members, as well as to reject first-person assent and "presumed consent" policies of organ procurement. Insofar as individuals have failed clearly and competently to provide informed consent to organ donation, moral authorization for the use of the person and his body ought to be grounded on the foundational authority of the family, rather than the state's supposed interests in obtaining organs for transplantation.


Subject(s)
Family/psychology , Tissue and Organ Procurement/ethics , Tissue and Organ Procurement/legislation & jurisprudence , Decision Making , Humans , Informed Consent/psychology , Morals , Motivation , Philosophy, Medical
12.
J Med Philos ; 42(5): 503-517, 2017 Oct 01.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-28922907

ABSTRACT

The essays in this issue of The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy explore an innovative voucher program for encouraging kidney donation. Discussions cluster around a number of central moral and political/theoretical themes: (1) What are the direct and indirect health care costs and benefits of such a voucher system in human organs? (2) Do vouchers lead to more effective and efficient organ procurement and allocation or contribute to greater inequalities and inefficiencies in the transplantation system? (3) Do vouchers contribute to the inappropriate commodification of human body parts? (4) Is there a significant moral difference between such a voucher system and a market in human organs for transplantation? This paper argues that while kidney vouchers constitute a step in the right direction, fuller utilization of market-based incentives, including, but not limited to, barter exchanges (e.g., organ exchanges, organ chains, and organ vouchers), would save more lives and further reduce human suffering.


Subject(s)
Commodification , Health Care Costs , Kidney , Tissue and Organ Procurement , Humans , Moral Status , Morals , Tissue and Organ Procurement/methods , Tissue and Organ Procurement/organization & administration
13.
J Med Philos ; 41(5): 435-43, 2016 Oct.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-27473410

ABSTRACT

Two clusters of essays in this issue of The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy provide a critical gaze through which to explore central moral, phenomenological, ontological, and political concerns regarding human moral agency and personal responsibility. The first cluster challenges common assumptions in bioethics regarding the voluntariness of human actions. The second set turns the debate towards morally responsible choice within the requirements of distributive justice. The force of their collective analysis leaves us with a well-founded basis critically to approach any account of bioethics or health policy that is insufficiently attentive to the central challenges of human freedom and responsible free choice.


Subject(s)
Bioethical Issues , Moral Obligations , Social Responsibility , Bioethics , Freedom , Health Policy , Human Rights , Humans , Personal Autonomy , Philosophy, Medical
14.
J Med Philos ; 40(5): 473-83, 2015 Oct.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-26242446

ABSTRACT

This issue of The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy assesses the deep and abiding tensions that exist among the competing epistemic perspectives that bear on medicine and morality. Concepts of health and disease, as well as the theoretical framing of medical ethics and health care policy, intersect with an overlapping set of culturally situated communities (scientific, political, moral, and religious), striving to understand and manipulate the world in ways that each finds explanatory, appropriate, or otherwise befitting. The articles explore the complexities of framing public health care policy to guide bioethical decision making in the face of the plurality of ethical viewpoints and moral rationalities--including health enhancing supplements, continuous sedation until death, medical futility, the protection of vulnerable populations, and competing professional obligations.


Subject(s)
Ethical Analysis , Ethics, Medical , Morals , Decision Making , Health Policy , Humans , Medical Futility/ethics , Philosophy, Medical , Vulnerable Populations
16.
J Med Philos ; 40(4): 451-72, 2015 Aug.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-26069283

ABSTRACT

This paper challenges the foundational claim that the human family is no more than a social construction. It advances the position that the family is a central category of experience, being, and knowledge. Throughout, the analysis argues for the centrality of the family for human flourishing and, consequently, for the importance of sustaining (or reestablishing) family-oriented practices within social policy, such as more family-oriented approaches to consent to medical treatment. Where individually oriented approaches to medical decision-making accent an ethos of isolated personal autonomy family-oriented approaches acknowledge the central social and moral reality of the family. I argue that the family ought to be appreciated as more than a mere network of personal relations and individual undertakings; the family possesses a being that is social and moral such that it realizes a particular structure of human good and sustains the necessary conditions for core areas of human flourishing. Moreover, since the family exists as a nexus of face-to-face relationships, the consent of persons, including adults, to be members of a particular family, subject to its own respective account of family sovereignty, is significantly more amply demonstrated than the consent of citizens to be under the authority of a particular state. As a result, in the face of a general Western bioethical affirmation of the autonomy of individuals, as if adults and children were morally and socially isolated agents, this paper argues that social space must nevertheless be made for families to choose on behalf of their own members.


Subject(s)
Decision Making , Family/ethnology , Informed Consent/psychology , China , Culture , Family Relations , Humans , Morals , Personal Autonomy
18.
J Med Philos ; 38(3): 315-31, 2013 Jun.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23615058

ABSTRACT

In Roper v. Simmons (2005) the United States Supreme Court announced a paradigm shift in jurisprudence. Drawing specifically on mounting scientific evidence that adolescents are qualitatively different from adults in their decision-making capacities, the Supreme Court recognized that adolescents are not adults in all but age. The Court concluded that the overwhelming weight of the psychological and neurophysiological data regarding brain maturation supports the conclusion that adolescents are qualitatively different types of agents than adult persons. The Supreme Court further solidified its position regarding adolescents as less than fully mature and responsible decisionmakers in Graham v. Florida (2010) and Miller v. Alabama (2012). In each case, the Court concluded that the scientific evidence does not support the conclusion that children under 18 years of age possess adult capacities for personal agency, rationality, and mature choice. This study explores the implications of the Supreme Court decisions in Roper v. Simmons, Graham v. Florida, and Miller v. Alabama for the "mature minor" standard for medical decision making. It argues that the Supreme Court's holdings in Roper, Graham, and Miller require no less than a radical reassessment of how healthcare institutions, courts of law, and public policy are obliged to regard minors as medical decisionmakers. The "mature minor" standard for medical decision making must be abandoned.


Subject(s)
Adolescent Development , Informed Consent/ethics , Informed Consent/legislation & jurisprudence , Mental Competency/legislation & jurisprudence , Minors/psychology , Adolescent , Brain/growth & development , Canada , Cognition , Decision Making , Humans , Supreme Court Decisions , United States
19.
J Med Philos ; 37(6): 526-44, 2012 Dec.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-23178331

ABSTRACT

Despite the well-documented social, economic, and adaptive advantages for young children, adolescents, and adults, the traditional family in the West is in decline. A growing percentage of men and women choose not to be bound by the traditional moral and social expectations of marriage and family life. Adults are much more likely than in the past to live as sexually active singles, with a concomitant increase in forms of social isolation as well as in the number of children born outside of marriage. These social shifts are also connected to public policies that provide incentives for individuals to exit the family, leaving behind its social, capital, and economic resources. The individualistic character of the social-democratic egalitarian ideology that underlies the current dominant approaches to health care financing in Western Europe and much of North America, for example, is associated with a decline in family stability. Welfare entitlements, including state-based health care, have made it easier to exit the family, undermining the centrality of the family's core human relationships. This essay argues for the importance of recognizing the cardinal role and reality of the family and for the importance of family-based health care savings accounts for preserving family integrity, while also providing for sustainable long-term health care reform.


Subject(s)
Financing, Personal/statistics & numerical data , Insurance, Health/economics , Medical Savings Accounts/statistics & numerical data , Social Welfare/statistics & numerical data , Adolescent , Adult , Child , Community Participation/statistics & numerical data , Developed Countries , Female , Health Behavior , Health Benefit Plans, Employee/statistics & numerical data , Health Services Needs and Demand/statistics & numerical data , Humans , Male , Middle Aged , North America , Reimbursement Mechanisms/statistics & numerical data , Residence Characteristics , Social Change
20.
J Law Med Ethics ; 38(4): 789-98, 2010.
Article in English | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-21105942

ABSTRACT

Commentators routinely urge that it is morally permissible forcibly to treat psychiatric patients (1) to preserve the patient's best interests and (2) to restore the patient's autonomy. Such arguments specify duties of beneficence toward others, while appreciating personal autonomy as a positive value to be weighted against other factors. Varying by jurisdiction, legal statutes usually require, in addition, at least (3) that there exists the threat of harm to self or others. In this paper, I argue against embracing the first two elements of this prevailing view. I also argue for a very restricted reading of the third element, based on the moral limits of permissible state action.


Subject(s)
Coercion , Informed Consent/ethics , Mental Disorders/therapy , Morals , Treatment Refusal , Commitment of Mentally Ill/legislation & jurisprudence , Human Rights/legislation & jurisprudence , Humans , Informed Consent/legislation & jurisprudence , Medication Adherence , Mental Competency/legislation & jurisprudence , Personal Autonomy , United States
SELECTION OF CITATIONS
SEARCH DETAIL
...