Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Mostrar: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 20 de 191
Filtrar
1.
BMJ Open ; 14(4): e083453, 2024 Apr 29.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38684262

RESUMEN

INTRODUCTION: Opioid agonist treatment (OAT) tapering involves a gradual reduction in daily medication dose to ultimately reach a state of opioid abstinence. Due to the high risk of relapse and overdose after tapering, this practice is not recommended by clinical guidelines, however, clients may still request to taper off medication. The ideal time to initiate an OAT taper is not known. However, ethically, taper plans should acknowledge clients' preferences and autonomy but apply principles of shared informed decision-making regarding safety and efficacy. Linked population-level data capturing real-world tapering practices provide a valuable opportunity to improve existing evidence on when to contemplate starting an OAT taper. Our objective is to determine the comparative effectiveness of alternative times from OAT initiation at which a taper can be initiated, with a primary outcome of taper completion, as observed in clinical practice in British Columbia (BC), Canada. METHODS AND ANALYSIS: We propose a population-level retrospective observational study with a linkage of eight provincial health administrative databases in BC, Canada (01 January 2010 to 17 March 2020). Our primary outcomes include taper completion and all-cause mortality during treatment. We propose a 'per-protocol' target trial to compare different durations to taper initiation on the likelihood of taper completion. A range of sensitivity analyses will be used to assess the heterogeneity and robustness of the results including assessment of effectiveness and safety. ETHICS AND DISSEMINATION: The protocol, cohort creation and analysis plan have been classified and approved as a quality improvement initiative by Providence Health Care Research Ethics Board and the Simon Fraser University Office of Research Ethics. Results will be disseminated to local advocacy groups and decision-makers, national and international clinical guideline developers, presented at international conferences and published in peer-reviewed journals electronically and in print.


Asunto(s)
Tratamiento de Sustitución de Opiáceos , Trastornos Relacionados con Opioides , Humanos , Colombia Británica , Estudios Retrospectivos , Trastornos Relacionados con Opioides/tratamiento farmacológico , Tratamiento de Sustitución de Opiáceos/métodos , Analgésicos Opioides/administración & dosificación , Analgésicos Opioides/uso terapéutico , Reducción Gradual de Medicamentos , Investigación sobre la Eficacia Comparativa , Factores de Tiempo , Proyectos de Investigación
2.
NEJM Evid ; 3(1): EVIDoa2300003, 2024 Jan.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38320512

RESUMEN

A New Look at P Values for Randomized Clinical TrialsUsing the primary results of 23,551 randomized clinical trials from the Cochrane Database, van Zwet et al. provide an empirical guide for the interpretation of an observed P value from a "typical" clinical trial in terms of the degree of overestimation of the reported effect, the probability of the effect's sign being wrong, and the predictive power of the trial.


Asunto(s)
Ensayos Clínicos Controlados Aleatorios como Asunto
4.
JAMA ; 331(4): 285-286, 2024 01 23.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38175628

RESUMEN

This Viewpoint argues that a hypothesis-centric approach to writing grant applications is problematic and instead suggests that funding applications should be evaluated by their relevance and methodological quality rather than by qualitative assertions before the study is conducted.


Asunto(s)
Organización de la Financiación , Apoyo a la Investigación como Asunto , Escritura , Organización de la Financiación/métodos , Organización de la Financiación/normas , Apoyo a la Investigación como Asunto/métodos , Apoyo a la Investigación como Asunto/normas
5.
Epidemiology ; 35(2): 218-231, 2024 Mar 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-38290142

RESUMEN

BACKGROUND: Instrumental variable (IV) analysis provides an alternative set of identification assumptions in the presence of uncontrolled confounding when attempting to estimate causal effects. Our objective was to evaluate the suitability of measures of prescriber preference and calendar time as potential IVs to evaluate the comparative effectiveness of buprenorphine/naloxone versus methadone for treatment of opioid use disorder (OUD). METHODS: Using linked population-level health administrative data, we constructed five IVs: prescribing preference at the individual, facility, and region levels (continuous and categorical variables), calendar time, and a binary prescriber's preference IV in analyzing the treatment assignment-treatment discontinuation association using both incident-user and prevalent-new-user designs. Using published guidelines, we assessed and compared each IV according to the four assumptions for IVs, employing both empirical assessment and content expertise. We evaluated the robustness of results using sensitivity analyses. RESULTS: The study sample included 35,904 incident users (43.3% on buprenorphine/naloxone) initiated on opioid agonist treatment by 1585 prescribers during the study period. While all candidate IVs were strong (A1) according to conventional criteria, by expert opinion, we found no evidence against assumptions of exclusion (A2), independence (A3), monotonicity (A4a), and homogeneity (A4b) for prescribing preference-based IV. Some criteria were violated for the calendar time-based IV. We determined that preference in provider-level prescribing, measured on a continuous scale, was the most suitable IV for comparative effectiveness of buprenorphine/naloxone and methadone for the treatment of OUD. CONCLUSIONS: Our results suggest that prescriber's preference measures are suitable IVs in comparative effectiveness studies of treatment for OUD.


Asunto(s)
Metadona , Trastornos Relacionados con Opioides , Humanos , Metadona/uso terapéutico , Trastornos Relacionados con Opioides/tratamiento farmacológico , Combinación Buprenorfina y Naloxona/uso terapéutico , Tratamiento de Sustitución de Opiáceos/métodos , Estado de Salud , Analgésicos Opioides/uso terapéutico
6.
J Glob Health ; 13: 04101, 2023 Sep 15.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37712381

RESUMEN

Background: We noted that there remains some confusion in the health-science literature on reporting sample odds ratios as estimated rate ratios in case-control studies. Methods: We recap historical literature that definitively answered the question of when sample odds ratios (ORs) from a case-control study are consistent estimators for population rate ratios. We use numerical examples to illustrate the magnitude of the disparity between sample ORs in a case-control study and population rate ratios when sufficient conditions for them to be equal are not satisfied. Results: We stress that in a case-control study, sampling controls from those still at risk at the time of outcome event of the index case is not sufficient for a sample OR to be a consistent estimator for an intelligible rate ratio. In such studies, constancy of the exposure prevalence together with constancy of the hazard ratio (HR) (i.e., the instantaneous rate ratio) over time is sufficient for this result if sampling time is not controlled; if time is controlled, constancy of the HR will suffice. We present numerical examples to illustrate how failure to satisfy these conditions adds a small systematic error to sample ORs as estimates of population rate ratios. Conclusions: We recommend that researchers understand and critically evaluate all conditions used to interpret their estimates as consistent for a population parameter in case-control studies.


Asunto(s)
Investigadores , Humanos , Estudios de Casos y Controles , Oportunidad Relativa
8.
Eur J Epidemiol ; 37(11): 1149-1154, 2022 Nov.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36369315

RESUMEN

The 1970s and 1980s saw the appearance of many papers on the topics of synergy, antagonism, and similar concepts of causal interactions and interdependence of effects, with a special emphasis on distinguishing these concepts from that of statistical interaction - the need for a product term in a model. As an example, Miettinen defined "synergism" as "the existence of instances in which both risk factors are needed for the effect", whereas "antagonism" is where "at least one [factor] can block the solo effect of the other". In response, Greenland and Poole constructed a systematic analysis of 16 possible individual response patterns in a deterministic causal model for two binary exposure variables, and showed how these patterns can be mapped onto nine types of sufficient causes, which in turn can be simplified into four intuitive categories. Although these and other papers recognized that epidemiology cannot directly study biological mechanisms underlying interaction, they showed how it can usefully study causal and preventive interdependence - which, despite its mechanistic agnosticism, has important implications for clinical decision making as well as for public health.


Asunto(s)
Modelos Teóricos , Humanos , Causalidad , Factores de Riesgo
9.
Vaccine ; 40(40): 5798-5805, 2022 09 22.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36055877

RESUMEN

INTRODUCTION: In 2020, prior to COVID-19 vaccine rollout, the Brighton Collaboration created a priority list, endorsed by the World Health Organization, of potential adverse events relevant to COVID-19 vaccines. We adapted the Brighton Collaboration list to evaluate serious adverse events of special interest observed in mRNA COVID-19 vaccine trials. METHODS: Secondary analysis of serious adverse events reported in the placebo-controlled, phase III randomized clinical trials of Pfizer and Moderna mRNA COVID-19 vaccines in adults (NCT04368728 and NCT04470427), focusing analysis on Brighton Collaboration adverse events of special interest. RESULTS: Pfizer and Moderna mRNA COVID-19 vaccines were associated with an excess risk of serious adverse events of special interest of 10.1 and 15.1 per 10,000 vaccinated over placebo baselines of 17.6 and 42.2 (95 % CI -0.4 to 20.6 and -3.6 to 33.8), respectively. Combined, the mRNA vaccines were associated with an excess risk of serious adverse events of special interest of 12.5 per 10,000 vaccinated (95 % CI 2.1 to 22.9); risk ratio 1.43 (95 % CI 1.07 to 1.92). The Pfizer trial exhibited a 36 % higher risk of serious adverse events in the vaccine group; risk difference 18.0 per 10,000 vaccinated (95 % CI 1.2 to 34.9); risk ratio 1.36 (95 % CI 1.02 to 1.83). The Moderna trial exhibited a 6 % higher risk of serious adverse events in the vaccine group: risk difference 7.1 per 10,000 (95 % CI -23.2 to 37.4); risk ratio 1.06 (95 % CI 0.84 to 1.33). Combined, there was a 16 % higher risk of serious adverse events in mRNA vaccine recipients: risk difference 13.2 (95 % CI -3.2 to 29.6); risk ratio 1.16 (95 % CI 0.97 to 1.39). DISCUSSION: The excess risk of serious adverse events found in our study points to the need for formal harm-benefit analyses, particularly those that are stratified according to risk of serious COVID-19 outcomes. These analyses will require public release of participant level datasets.


Asunto(s)
COVID-19 , Vacunas , Adulto , COVID-19/prevención & control , Vacunas contra la COVID-19/efectos adversos , Humanos , ARN Mensajero , Ensayos Clínicos Controlados Aleatorios como Asunto , Vacunación/efectos adversos , Vacunas Sintéticas , Vacunas de ARNm
10.
Prev Med ; 164: 107127, 2022 11.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-35787846

RESUMEN

It is well known that the statistical analyses in health-science and medical journals are frequently misleading or even wrong. Despite many decades of reform efforts by hundreds of scientists and statisticians, attempts to fix the problem by avoiding obvious error and encouraging good practice have not altered this basic situation. Statistical teaching and reporting remain mired in damaging yet editorially enforced jargon of "significance", "confidence", and imbalanced focus on null (no-effect or "nil") hypotheses, leading to flawed attempts to simplify descriptions of results in ordinary terms. A positive development amidst all this has been the introduction of interval estimates alongside or in place of significance tests and P-values, but intervals have been beset by similar misinterpretations. Attempts to remedy this situation by calling for replacement of traditional statistics with competitors (such as pure-likelihood or Bayesian methods) have had little impact. Thus, rather than ban or replace P-values or confidence intervals, we propose to replace traditional jargon with more accurate and modest ordinary-language labels that describe these statistics as measures of compatibility between data and hypotheses or models, which have long been in use in the statistical modeling literature. Such descriptions emphasize the full range of possibilities compatible with observations. Additionally, a simple transform of the P-value called the surprisal or S-value provides a sense of how much or how little information the data supply against those possibilities. We illustrate these reforms using some examples from a highly charged topic: trials of ivermectin treatment for Covid-19.


Asunto(s)
COVID-19 , Humanos , Interpretación Estadística de Datos , Teorema de Bayes , COVID-19/prevención & control , Probabilidad , Modelos Estadísticos , Intervalos de Confianza
12.
Trends Ecol Evol ; 37(7): 567-568, 2022 Jul.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-35227533
13.
JAMA ; 327(11): 1083-1084, 2022 03 15.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-35226050
14.
J Clin Epidemiol ; 142: 294-304, 2022 02.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34390790

RESUMEN

OBJECTIVE: Recently Doi et al. argued that risk ratios should be replaced with odds ratios in clinical research. We disagreed, and empirically documented the lack of portability of odds ratios, while Doi et al. defended their position. In this response we highlight important errors in their position. STUDY DESIGN AND SETTING: We counter Doi et al.'s arguments by further examining the correlations of odds ratios, and risk ratios, with baseline risks in 20,198 meta-analyses from the Cochrane Database of Systematic Reviews. RESULTS: Doi et al.'s claim that odds ratios are portable is invalid because 1) their reasoning is circular: they assume a model under which the odds ratio is constant and show that under such a model the odds ratio is portable; 2) the method they advocate to convert odds ratios to risk ratios is biased; 3) their empirical example is readily-refuted by counter-examples of meta-analyses in which the risk ratio is portable but the odds ratio isn't; and 4) they fail to consider the causal determinants of meta-analytic inclusion criteria: Doi et al. mistakenly claim that variation in odds ratios with different baseline risks in meta-analyses is due to collider bias. Empirical comparison between the correlations of odds ratios, and risk ratios, with baseline risks show that the portability of odds ratios and risk ratios varies across settings. CONCLUSION: The suggestion to replace risk ratios with odds ratios is based on circular reasoning and a confusion of mathematical and empirical results. It is especially misleading for meta-analyses and clinical guidance. Neither the odds ratio nor the risk ratio is universally portable. To address this lack of portability, we reinforce our suggestion to report variation in effect measures conditioning on modifying factors such as baseline risk; understanding such variation is essential to patient-centered practice.


Asunto(s)
Oportunidad Relativa , Sesgo , Causalidad , Humanos , Riesgo , Revisiones Sistemáticas como Asunto
15.
Epidemiology ; 32(5): 617-624, 2021 09 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34224472

RESUMEN

Quantitative bias analyses allow researchers to adjust for uncontrolled confounding, given specification of certain bias parameters. When researchers are concerned about unknown confounders, plausible values for these bias parameters will be difficult to specify. Ding and VanderWeele developed bounding factor and E-value approaches that require the user to specify only some of the bias parameters. We describe the mathematical meaning of bounding factors and E-values and the plausibility of these methods in an applied context. We encourage researchers to pay particular attention to the assumption made, when using E-values, that the prevalence of the uncontrolled confounder among the exposed is 100% (or, equivalently, the prevalence of the exposure among those without the confounder is 0%). We contrast methods that attempt to bound biases or effects and alternative approaches such as quantitative bias analysis. We provide an example where failure to make this distinction led to erroneous statements. If the primary concern in an analysis is with known but unmeasured potential confounders, then E-values are not needed and may be misleading. In cases where the concern is with unknown confounders, the E-value assumption of an extreme possible prevalence of the confounder limits its practical utility.


Asunto(s)
Factores de Confusión Epidemiológicos , Sesgo , Humanos
16.
J Clin Epidemiol ; 138: 178-181, 2021 10.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34119646

RESUMEN

To prevent statistical misinterpretations, it has long been advised to focus on estimation instead of statistical testing. This sound advice brings with it the need to choose the outcome and effect measures on which to focus. Measures based on odds or their logarithms have often been promoted due to their pleasing statistical properties, but have an undesirable property for risk summarization and communication: Noncollapsibility, defined as a failure of the measure when taken on a group to equal a simple average of the measure when taken on the group's members or subgroups. The present note illustrates this problem with a basic numeric example involving the odds, which is not collapsible when the odds vary across individuals and are not low in all subgroups. Its sequel will illustrate how this problem is amplified in odds ratios and logistic regression.


Asunto(s)
Investigación Biomédica/estadística & datos numéricos , Exactitud de los Datos , Modelos Logísticos , Oportunidad Relativa , Sesgo de Publicación/estadística & datos numéricos , Proyectos de Investigación/estadística & datos numéricos , Factores de Confusión Epidemiológicos , Humanos
17.
J Clin Epidemiol ; 139: 264-268, 2021 11.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-34119647

RESUMEN

A previous note illustrated how the odds of an outcome have an undesirable property for risk summarization and communication: Noncollapsibility, defined as a failure of a group measure to represent a simple average of the measure over individuals or subgroups. The present sequel discusses how odds ratios amplify odds noncollapsibility and provides a basic numeric illustration of how noncollapsibility differs from confounding of effects (with which it is often confused). It also draws a connection of noncollapsibility to sparse-data bias in logistic, log-linear, and proportional-hazards regression.


Asunto(s)
Investigación Biomédica/normas , Exactitud de los Datos , Oportunidad Relativa , Sesgo de Publicación/estadística & datos numéricos , Proyectos de Investigación/normas , Investigadores/psicología , Investigación Biomédica/estadística & datos numéricos , Factores de Confusión Epidemiológicos , Humanos , Modelos Logísticos , Proyectos de Investigación/estadística & datos numéricos
18.
Am J Epidemiol ; 190(8): 1617-1621, 2021 08 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33778862

RESUMEN

Lash et al. (Am J Epidemiol. 2021;190(8):1604-1612) have presented detailed critiques of 3 bias analyses that they identify as "suboptimal." This identification raises the question of what "optimal" means for bias analysis, because it is practically impossible to do statistically optimal analyses of typical population studies-with or without bias analysis. At best the analysis can only attempt to satisfy practice guidelines and account for available information both within and outside the study. One should not expect a full accounting for all sources of uncertainty; hence, interval estimates and distributions for causal effects should never be treated as valid uncertainty assessments-they are instead only example analyses that follow from collections of often questionable assumptions. These observations reinforce those of Lash et al. and point to the need for more development of methods for judging bias-parameter distributions and utilization of available information.


Asunto(s)
Proyectos de Investigación , Sesgo , Causalidad , Humanos
19.
Am J Epidemiol ; 190(2): 191-193, 2021 02 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32648906

RESUMEN

Measures of information and surprise, such as the Shannon information value (S value), quantify the signal present in a stream of noisy data. We illustrate the use of such information measures in the context of interpreting P values as compatibility indices. S values help communicate the limited information supplied by conventional statistics and cast a critical light on cutoffs used to judge and construct those statistics. Misinterpretations of statistics may be reduced by interpreting P values and interval estimates using compatibility concepts and S values instead of "significance" and "confidence."


Asunto(s)
Interpretación Estadística de Datos , Métodos Epidemiológicos , Intervalos de Confianza , Humanos , Incertidumbre
20.
Paediatr Perinat Epidemiol ; 35(1): 8-23, 2021 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-33269490

RESUMEN

The "replication crisis" has been attributed to perverse incentives that lead to selective reporting and misinterpretations of P-values and confidence intervals. A crude fix offered for this problem is to lower testing cut-offs (α levels), either directly or in the form of null-biased multiple comparisons procedures such as naïve Bonferroni adjustments. Methodologists and statisticians have expressed positions that range from condemning all such procedures to demanding their application in almost all analyses. Navigating between these unjustifiable extremes requires defining analysis goals precisely enough to separate inappropriate from appropriate adjustments. To meet this need, I here review issues arising in single-parameter inference (such as error costs and loss functions) that are often skipped in basic statistics, yet are crucial to understanding controversies in testing and multiple comparisons. I also review considerations that should be made when examining arguments for and against modifications of decision cut-offs and adjustments for multiple comparisons. The goal is to provide researchers a better understanding of what is assumed by each side and to enable recognition of hidden assumptions. Basic issues of goal specification and error costs are illustrated with simple fixed cut-off hypothesis testing scenarios. These illustrations show how adjustment choices are extremely sensitive to implicit decision costs, making it inevitable that different stakeholders will vehemently disagree about what is necessary or appropriate. Because decisions cannot be justified without explicit costs, resolution of inference controversies is impossible without recognising this sensitivity. Pre-analysis statements of funding, scientific goals, and analysis plans can help counter demands for inappropriate adjustments, and can provide guidance as to what adjustments are advisable. Hierarchical (multilevel) regression methods (including Bayesian, semi-Bayes, and empirical-Bayes methods) provide preferable alternatives to conventional adjustments, insofar as they facilitate use of background information in the analysis model, and thus can provide better-informed estimates on which to base inferences and decisions.


Asunto(s)
Objetivos , Proyectos de Investigación , Teorema de Bayes , Humanos
SELECCIÓN DE REFERENCIAS
DETALLE DE LA BÚSQUEDA
...