Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Mostrar: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 6 de 6
Filtrar
Mais filtros











Base de dados
Intervalo de ano de publicação
1.
Behav Brain Sci ; 46: e292, 2023 09 28.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-37766639

RESUMO

The target article attempted to draw connections between broad swaths of evidence by noticing a common thread: Abstract, symbolic, compositional codes, that is, language-of-thoughts (LoTs). Commentators raised concerns about the evidence and offered fascinating extensions to areas we overlooked. Here we respond and highlight the many specific empirical questions to be answered in the next decade and beyond.


Assuntos
Ciência Cognitiva , Idioma , Humanos
2.
JAMA Psychiatry ; 80(1): 8-9, 2023 01 01.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36350609

RESUMO

This Viewpoint highlights how new insights into belief acquisition, storage, and change can transform our understanding of psychiatric disorders.


Assuntos
Transtornos Mentais , Saúde Mental , Humanos , Transtornos Mentais/diagnóstico , Transtornos Mentais/terapia , Transtornos Mentais/psicologia , Religião e Psicologia , Ciência Cognitiva
3.
Cogn Sci ; 46(12): e13225, 2022 12.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36537721

RESUMO

"What is the structure of thought?" is as central a question as any in cognitive science. A classic answer to this question has appealed to a Language of Thought (LoT). We point to emerging research from disparate branches of the field that supports the LoT hypothesis, but also uncovers diversity in LoTs across cognitive systems, stages of development, and species. Our letter formulates open research questions for cognitive science concerning the varieties of rules and representations that underwrite various LoT-based systems and how these variations can help researchers taxonomize cognitive systems.


Assuntos
Ciência Cognitiva , Idioma , Humanos
4.
Behav Brain Sci ; 46: e261, 2022 12 06.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-36471543

RESUMO

Mental representations remain the central posits of psychology after many decades of scrutiny. However, there is no consensus about the representational format(s) of biological cognition. This paper provides a survey of evidence from computational cognitive psychology, perceptual psychology, developmental psychology, comparative psychology, and social psychology, and concludes that one type of format that routinely crops up is the language-of-thought (LoT). We outline six core properties of LoTs: (i) discrete constituents; (ii) role-filler independence; (iii) predicate-argument structure; (iv) logical operators; (v) inferential promiscuity; and (vi) abstract content. These properties cluster together throughout cognitive science. Bayesian computational modeling, compositional features of object perception, complex infant and animal reasoning, and automatic, intuitive cognition in adults all implicate LoT-like structures. Instead of regarding LoT as a relic of the previous century, researchers in cognitive science and philosophy-of-mind must take seriously the explanatory breadth of LoT-based architectures. We grant that the mind may harbor many formats and architectures, including iconic and associative structures as well as deep-neural-network-like architectures. However, as computational/representational approaches to the mind continue to advance, classical compositional symbolic structures - that is, LoTs - only prove more flexible and well-supported over time.


Assuntos
Cognição , Idioma , Adulto , Animais , Humanos , Teorema de Bayes , Ciência Cognitiva
5.
Wiley Interdiscip Rev Cogn Sci ; 12(2): e1539, 2021 Mar.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-32627423

RESUMO

The empirical study of belief is emerging at a rapid clip, uniting work from all corners of cognitive science. Reliance on belief in understanding and predicting behavior is widespread. Examples can be found, inter alia, in the placebo, attribution theory, theory of mind, and comparative psychological literatures. Research on belief also provides evidence for robust generalizations, including about how we fix, store, and change our beliefs. Evidence supports the existence of a Spinozan system of belief fixation: one that is automatic and independent of belief rejection. Independent research supports the existence of a system of fragmented belief storage: one that relies on large numbers of causally isolated, context-sensitive stores of belief in memory. Finally, empirical and observational data support at least two systems of belief change. One system adheres, mostly, to epistemological norms of updating; the other, the psychological immune system, functions to guard our most centrally held beliefs from potential inconsistency with newly formed beliefs. Refining our understanding of these systems can shed light on pressing real-world issues, such as how fake news, propaganda, and brainwashing exploit our psychology of belief, and how best to construct our modern informational world. This article is categorized under: Psychology > Reasoning and Decision Making Philosophy > Knowledge and Belief Philosophy > Foundations of Cognitive Science.


Assuntos
Ciência Cognitiva , Conhecimento , Filosofia , Teoria da Mente , Humanos , Relatório de Pesquisa
6.
Cogn Sci ; 2018 Apr 24.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-29687466

RESUMO

Experiments on theories of reference have mostly tested referential intuitions. We think that experiments should rather be testing linguistic usage. Substantive Aim (I): to test classical description theories of proper names against usage by "elicited production." Our results count decisively against those theories. Methodological Aim (I): Machery, Olivola, and de Blanc () claim that truth-value judgment experiments test usage. Martí () disagrees. We argue that Machery et al. are right and offer some results that are consistent with that conclusion. Substantive Aim (II): Machery et al. provide evidence that the usage of a name varies, being sometimes descriptive, sometimes not. In seven out of eight tests of usage, we did not replicate this variation. Methodological Aim (II): to test the reliability of referential intuitions by comparing them with linguistic usage. Earlier studies led us to predict that we would find those intuitions unreliable, but we did not. Our results add to evidence that tests of referential intuition are susceptible to unpredictable wording effects.

SELEÇÃO DE REFERÊNCIAS
DETALHE DA PESQUISA