Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Show: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 20 de 24
Filtrar
1.
Artículo en Alemán | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22015792

RESUMEN

With the introduction and recommendation of the new HPV (human papillomavirus) vaccination in 2007, cervical cancer prevention has evoked large public interest. Is the public able to make informed decisions on the basis of media reports and brochures? To answer this question, an analysis of media coverage of HPV vaccination (Gardasil®) and Pap (Papanicolaou) screening was conducted from 2007-2009, which investigated the minimum requirement of completeness (pros and cons), transparency (absolute numbers), and correctness (references concerning outcome, uncertainty, magnitude) of the information. As a bench mark, facts boxes with concise data on epidemiology, etiology, benefits, harms, and costs were compiled in advance. Although all vaccination reports and brochures covered the impact of prevention, only 41% provided concrete numbers on effectiveness (90/220) and 2% on absolute risk reductions for the cancer surrogate dysplasia (5/220), whereby none of the latter numbers was correct. The prevention potential was correctly presented once. Only 48% (105/220) mentioned pros and cons. With regard to screening, 20% (4/20) provided explicit data on test quality and one expressed these in absolute numbers, while 25% (5/20) reported the prevention potential; all given numbers were correct. Finally, 25% (5/20) mentioned the possibility of false positive results. Minimum requirements were fulfilled by 1/220 vaccination and 1/20 screening reports. At present, informed decision making based on media coverage is hardly possible.


Asunto(s)
Toma de Decisiones , Educación en Salud , Conocimientos, Actitudes y Práctica en Salud , Medios de Comunicación de Masas , Folletos , Prueba de Papanicolaou , Infecciones por Papillomavirus/prevención & control , Vacunas contra Papillomavirus/administración & dosificación , Neoplasias del Cuello Uterino/prevención & control , Frotis Vaginal , Adolescente , Adulto , Niño , Femenino , Alemania , Vacuna Tetravalente Recombinante contra el Virus del Papiloma Humano Tipos 6, 11 , 16, 18 , Humanos , Aceptación de la Atención de Salud , Conducta de Reducción del Riesgo , Adulto Joven
2.
Artículo en Alemán | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-21161479

RESUMEN

The influenza pandemic (H1N1) 2009 showed that many decision and policy makers do not trust citizens to effectively cope with uncertainty. We discuss three fundamental problems with the information management at the time: (1) knowledge of available and missing evidence was not communicated transparently and completely, (2) rather than informing citizens, officials often treated them paternalistically, and (3) public trust in vaccinations and institutions was damaged as a result of (1) and (2). We suggest the following measures to policy and decision makers in order to avoid similar problems in the future: transparent description of the situation instead of buzzwords such as "pandemic;" transparent communication of existing and missing evidence instead of dramatic estimates of death rates; disclosure of political decision processes and conflicts of interest.


Asunto(s)
Planificación en Desastres/organización & administración , Subtipo H1N1 del Virus de la Influenza A , Gripe Humana/epidemiología , Gripe Humana/prevención & control , Pandemias/prevención & control , Competencia Profesional , Administración en Salud Pública , Alemania/epidemiología , Humanos , Vacunas contra la Influenza/provisión & distribución , Difusión de la Información/métodos , Pandemias/estadística & datos numéricos , Vigilancia de la Población/métodos , Medición de Riesgo , Gestión de Riesgos/métodos
3.
Science ; 290(5500): 2261-2, 2000 Dec 22.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-11188724

RESUMEN

Most people, experts included, have difficulties understanding and combining statistical information effectively. Hoffrage et al. demonstrate that these difficulties can be considerably reduced by communicating the information in terms of natural frequencies rather than in terms of probabilities. Several applications in medicine, legal decision-making, and education are discussed.


Asunto(s)
Dermatoglifia del ADN , Interpretación Estadística de Datos , Técnicas y Procedimientos Diagnósticos , Probabilidad , Estadística como Asunto , Humanos , Valor Predictivo de las Pruebas , Medición de Riesgo , Sensibilidad y Especificidad
4.
Ther Umsch ; 64(12): 687-92, 2007 Dec.
Artículo en Alemán | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-18581918

RESUMEN

An understanding of risk requires an understanding of probabilities and a minimum of statistical thinking. This understanding is the basis of an adequate risk communication, which is especially important in the field of medicine. Every day a practicing doctor is confronted with the question of how likely a patient is to have a disease when tested positive. Clinicians are not only asked to provide a correct answer to their patients but also a comprehensible one, if they want to assure that a patient is enabled to make an informed decision. Several studies suggest, however that clinicians struggle somewhat to come up with correct judgments concerning this issue and tend to heavily overestimate the risk. We will argue in this article that this problem is mainly based on how risks are presented. We will reveal some of the common pitfalls and make suggestions on how to interpret and communicate risks in an easy fashion.


Asunto(s)
Neoplasias de la Mama/epidemiología , Comunicación , Indicadores de Salud , Relaciones Médico-Paciente , Neoplasias de la Mama/diagnóstico , Neoplasias de la Mama/prevención & control , Interpretación Estadística de Datos , Femenino , Humanos , Persona de Mediana Edad , Valor Predictivo de las Pruebas , Probabilidad , Conducta de Reducción del Riesgo
5.
Trends Cogn Sci ; 2(6): 206-14, 1998 Jun 01.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-21227174

RESUMEN

The classical view that equates rationality with adherence to the laws of probability theory and logic has driven much research on inference. Recently, an increasing number of researchers have begun to espouse a view of rationality that takes account of organisms' adaptive goals, natural environments, and cognitive constraints. We argue that inference is carried out using boundedly rational heuristics, that is, heuristics that allow organisms to reach their goals under conditions of limited time, information, and computational capacity. These heuristics are ecologically rational in that they exploit aspects of both the physical and social environment in order to make adaptive inferences. We review recent work exploring this multifaceted conception of rationality.

6.
Psychol Rev ; 103(4): 650-69, 1996 Oct.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-8888650

RESUMEN

Humans and animals make inferences about the world under limited time and knowledge. In contrast, many models of rational inference treat the mind as a Laplacean Demon, equipped with unlimited time, knowledge, and computational might. Following H. Simon's notion of satisfying, the authors have proposed a family of algorithms based on a simple psychological mechanism: one-reason decision making. These fast and frugal algorithms violate fundamental tenets of classical rationality: They neither look up nor integrate all information. By computer simulation, the authors held a competition between the satisfying "Take The Best" algorithm and various "rational" inference procedures (e.g., multiple regression). The Take The Best algorithm matched or outperformed all competitors in inferential speed and accuracy. This result in an existence proof that cognitive mechanisms capable of successful performance in the real world do not need to satisfy the classical norms of rational inference.


Asunto(s)
Algoritmos , Simulación por Computador , Toma de Decisiones , Solución de Problemas , Animales , Señales (Psicología) , Humanos , Tiempo de Reacción , Medio Social
7.
Psychol Rev ; 98(4): 506-28, 1991 Oct.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-1961771

RESUMEN

Research on people's confidence in their general knowledge has to date produced two fairly stable effects, many inconsistent results, and no comprehensive theory. We propose such a comprehensive framework, the theory of probabilistic mental models (PMM theory). The theory (a) explains both the overconfidence effect (mean confidence is higher than percentage of answers correct) and the hard-easy effect (overconfidence increases with item difficulty) reported in the literature and (b) predicts conditions under which both effects appear, disappear, or invert. In addition, (c) it predicts a new phenomenon, the confidence-frequency effect, a systematic difference between a judgment of confidence in a single event (i.e., that any given answer is correct) and a judgment of the frequency of correct answers in the long run. Two experiments are reported that support PMM theory by confirming these predictions, and several apparent anomalies reported in the literature are explained and integrated into the present framework.


Asunto(s)
Juicio , Teoría de la Probabilidad , Autoimagen , Adulto , Humanos
8.
Cognition ; 81(1): 93-103; discussion 105-11, 2001 Aug.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-11525483

RESUMEN

In the psychology of thinking, little thought is given to what constitutes good thinking. Instead, normative solutions to problems have been accepted at face value, thereby determining what counts as a reasoning fallacy. I applaud Vranas (Cognition 76 (2000) 179) for thinking seriously about norms. I do, however, disagree with his attempt to provide post hoc justifications for supposed reasoning fallacies in terms of 'content-neutral' norms. Norms need to be constructed for a specific situation, not imposed upon it in a content-blind way. The reason is that content-blind norms disregard relevant structural properties of the given situation, including polysemy, reference classes, and sampling. I also show that content-blind norms can, unwittingly, lead to double standards: the norm in one problem is the fallacy in the next. The alternative to content-blind norms is not no norms, but rather carefully designed norms.


Asunto(s)
Cognición , Modelos Psicológicos , Probabilidad , Humanos , Valores de Referencia
9.
Cognition ; 43(2): 127-71, 1992 May.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-1617917

RESUMEN

What counts as human rationality: reasoning processes that embody content-independent formal theories, such as propositional logic, or reasoning processes that are well designed for solving important adaptive problems? Most theories of human reasoning have been based on content-independent formal rationality, whereas adaptive reasoning, ecological or evolutionary, has been little explored. We elaborate and test an evolutionary approach. Cosmides' (1989) social contract theory, using the Wason selection task. In the first part, we disentangle the theoretical concept of a "social contract" from that of a "cheater-detection algorithm". We demonstrate that the fact that a rule is perceived as a social contract--or a conditional permission or obligation, as Cheng and Holyoak (1985) proposed--is not sufficient to elicit Cosmides' striking results, which we replicated. The crucial issue is not semantic (the meaning of the rule), but pragmatic: whether a person is cued into the perspective of a party who can be cheated. In the second part, we distinguish between social contracts with bilateral and unilateral cheating options. Perspective change in contracts with bilateral cheating options turns P & not-Q responses into not-P & Q responses. The results strongly support social contract theory, contradict availability theory, and cannot be accounted for by pragmatic reasoning schema theory, which lacks the pragmatic concepts of perspectives and cheating detection.


Asunto(s)
Cognición , Modelos Psicológicos , Conducta Social , Adulto , Toma de Decisiones , Femenino , Humanos , Relaciones Interpersonales , Lógica , Masculino , Probabilidad , Solución de Problemas , Análisis y Desempeño de Tareas , Pensamiento
10.
J Exp Psychol Gen ; 130(3): 380-400, 2001 Sep.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-11561916

RESUMEN

The authors present and test a new method of teaching Bayesian reasoning, something about which previous teaching studies reported little success. Based on G. Gigerenzer and U. Hoffrage's (1995) ecological framework, the authors wrote a computerized tutorial program to train people to construct frequency representations (representation training) rather than to insert probabilities into Bayes's rule (rule training). Bayesian computations are simpler to perform with natural frequencies than with probabilities, and there are evolutionary reasons for assuming that cognitive algorithms have been developed to deal with natural frequencies. In 2 studies, the authors compared representation training with rule training; the criteria were an immediate learning effect, transfer to new problems, and long-term temporal stability. Rule training was as good in transfer as representation training, but representation training had a higher immediate learning effect and greater temporal stability.


Asunto(s)
Teorema de Bayes , Instrucción por Computador , Aprendizaje por Probabilidad , Algoritmos , Humanos , Cómputos Matemáticos , Programas Informáticos
11.
Psychopharmacology (Berl) ; 142(3): 295-301, 1999 Mar.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-10208322

RESUMEN

RATIONALE AND OBJECTIVE: The present study tested the hypothesis that chronic interference by cannabis with endogenous cannabinoid systems during peripubertal development causes specific and persistent brain alterations in humans. As an index of cannabinoid action, visual scanning, along with other attentional functions, was chosen. Visual scanning undergoes a major maturation process around age 12-15 years and, in addition, the visual system is known to react specifically and sensitively to cannabinoids. METHODS: From 250 individuals consuming cannabis regularly, 99 healthy pure cannabis users were selected. They were free of any other past or present drug abuse, or history of neuropsychiatric disease. After an interview, physical examination, analysis of routine laboratory parameters, plasma/urine analyses for drugs, and MMPI testing, users and respective controls were subjected to a computer-assisted attention test battery comprising visual scanning, alertness, divided attention, flexibility, and working memory. RESULTS: Of the potential predictors of test performance within the user group, including present age, age of onset of cannabis use, degree of acute intoxication (THC+THCOH plasma levels), and cumulative toxicity (estimated total life dose), an early age of onset turned out to be the only predictor, predicting impaired reaction times exclusively in visual scanning. Early-onset users (onset before age 16; n = 48) showed a significant impairment in reaction times in this function, whereas late-onset users (onset after age 16; n = 51) did not differ from controls (n = 49). CONCLUSIONS: These data suggest that beginning cannabis use during early adolescence may lead to enduring effects on specific attentional functions in adulthood. Apparently, vulnerable periods during brain development exist that are subject to persistent alterations by interfering exogenous cannabinoids.


Asunto(s)
Trastorno por Déficit de Atención con Hiperactividad/inducido químicamente , Cannabis/efectos adversos , Adolescente , Adulto , Factores de Edad , Edad de Inicio , Atención/efectos de los fármacos , Trastorno por Déficit de Atención con Hiperactividad/epidemiología , Cannabinoides/metabolismo , Niño , Femenino , Humanos , Masculino , Tiempo de Reacción/efectos de los fármacos
12.
Science ; 244(4908): 1094-5, 1989 Jun 02.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-17741045
13.
J Exp Psychol Hum Percept Perform ; 9(1): 126-36, 1983 Feb.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-6220118

RESUMEN

In recent years there has been notable interest in additive models of sensory integration. Binaural additivity has emerged as a main hypothesis in the loudness-scaling literature and has recently been asserted by authors using an axiomatic approach to psychophysics. Restrictions of the range of stimuli used in the majority of former experiments, and inherent weaknesses of the axiomatic study by Levelt, Riemersma, and Bunt (1972) are discussed as providing reasons for the present investigation. A limited binaural additivity (LBA) model is proposed that assumes contralateral binaural inhibition for interaural intensity differences that exceed a critical level. Experimental data are reported for 12 subjects in a loudness-matching task designed to test the axioms of cancellation and of commutativity, both necessary to the existence of strict binaural additivity. In a 2 X 2 design, frequencies of 200 Hz and 2 kHz were used, and mean intensity levels were 20 dB apart. Additivity was found violated in 33 out of 48 possible tests. The LBA model is shown to predict the systematic nonadditivity in the loudness judgments and to conform to results from other studies.


Asunto(s)
Percepción Sonora , Femenino , Humanos , Masculino , Matemática , Modelos Psicológicos , Psicoacústica
14.
Acad Med ; 73(5): 538-40, 1998 May.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-9609869

RESUMEN

PURPOSE: To test whether physician's diagnostic inferences can be improved by communicating information using natural frequencies instead of probabilities. Whereas probabilities and relative frequencies are normalized with respect to disease base rates, natural frequencies are not normalized. METHOD: The authors asked 48 physicians in Munich and Düsseldorf to determine the positive predictive values (PPVs) of four diagnostic tests. Information presented in the four problems appeared either as probabilities (the traditional way) or as natural frequencies. RESULTS: When the information was presented as probabilities, the physicians correctly estimated the PPVs in only 10% of cases. When the same information was presented as natural frequencies, that percentage increased to 46%. CONCLUSION: Representing information in natural frequencies is a fast and effective way of facilitating diagnosis insight, which in turn helps physicians to better communicate risks to patients, and patients to better understand these risks.


Asunto(s)
Diagnóstico , Valor Predictivo de las Pruebas , Teorema de Bayes , Neoplasias de la Mama/diagnóstico por imagen , Reacciones Falso Positivas , Humanos , Mamografía , Probabilidad , Riesgo
15.
Med Decis Making ; 16(3): 273-80, 1996.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-8818126

RESUMEN

Mind and environment evolve in tandem--almost a platitude. Much of judgment and decision making research, however, has compared cognition to standard statistical models, rather than to how well it is adapted to its environment. The author argues two points. First, cognitive algorithms are tuned to certain information formats, most likely to those that humans have encountered during their evolutionary history. In particular, Bayesian computations are simpler when the information is in a frequency format than when it is in a probability format. The author investigates whether frequency formats can make physicians reason more often the Bayesian way. Second cognitive algorithms need to operate under constraints of limited time, knowledge, and computational power, and they need to exploit the structures of their environments. The author describes a fast and frugal algorithm. Take The Best, that violates standard principles of rational inference but can be as accurate as sophisticated "optimal" models for diagnostic inference.


Asunto(s)
Algoritmos , Cognición , Árboles de Decisión , Diagnóstico , Juicio , Médicos/psicología , Teorema de Bayes , Neoplasias de la Mama/diagnóstico por imagen , Ambiente , Femenino , Humanos , Lógica , Mamografía , Sensibilidad y Especificidad
16.
J Exp Psychol Learn Mem Cogn ; 26(3): 566-81, 2000 May.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-10855418

RESUMEN

With the benefit of feedback about the outcome of an event, people's recalled judgments are typically closer to the outcome of the event than their original judgments were. It has been suggested that this hindsight bias may be due to a reconstruction process of the prior judgment. A model of such a process is proposed that assumes that knowledge is updated after feedback and that reconstruction is based on the updated knowledge. Consistent with the model's predictions, the results of 2 studies show that knowledge after feedback is systematically shifted toward feedback, and that assisting retrieval of the knowledge prior to feedback reduces hindsight bias. In addition, the model accounts for about 75% of cases in which either hindsight bias or reversed hindsight bias occurred. The authors conclude that hindsight bias can be understood as a by-product of an adaptive process, namely the updating of knowledge after feedback.


Asunto(s)
Retroalimentación , Juicio , Conocimiento Psicológico de los Resultados , Recuerdo Mental , Adulto , Señales (Psicología) , Femenino , Humanos , Masculino , Memoria , Modelos Psicológicos
17.
Z Arztl Fortbild Qualitatssich ; 94(9): 713-9, 2000 Oct.
Artículo en Alemán | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-11127778

RESUMEN

Interpreting medical test results demands statistical reasoning on the part of doctors: How great is the probability of falsely diagnosing an illness based on a positive test result? This probability can be determined with the assistance of Bayes's Rule. Several studies show, however, that doctors often experience problems with these kinds of Bayesian inferences. We demonstrate that doctors' judgments can be considerably improved when numerical information is presented in a form easily accessible to the ways humans process information. This is not the case with the utilization of applied probabilities that has become customary, but is the case when the problem is presented in terms of "natural frequencies" that result from the counting of observed isolated cases in a natural environment. In a series of studies, we varied the representation format of the relevant statistical information. If the information was not presented in the form of probabilities or percentages but simply in natural frequencies, medical experts, as well as laymen, were able to improve their judgments significantly. And dealing with probabilities and percentages can also be easily learned: Two training programs, which showed how probabilities can be translated into natural frequencies, placed the participants in the position of being able to obtain very good results when solving these tasks. Finally, we discuss the impact of a comprehensible risk and utility communication on the doctor-patient relationship.


Asunto(s)
Pruebas Diagnósticas de Rutina , Educación Médica , Médicos , Teorema de Bayes , Humanos , Juicio
18.
Vaccine ; 32(12): 1388-93, 2014 Mar 10.
Artículo en Inglés | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-24486360

RESUMEN

OBJECTIVE: Informed decision making requires transparent and evidence-based (=balanced) information on the potential benefit and harms of medical preventions. An analysis of German HPV vaccination leaflets revealed, however, that none met the standards of balanced risk communication. METHODS: We surveyed a sample of 225 girl-parent pairs in a before-after design on the effects of balanced and unbalanced risk communication on participants' knowledge about cervical cancer and the HPV vaccination, their perceived risk, their intention to have the vaccine, and their actual vaccination decision. RESULTS: The balanced leaflet increased the number of participants who were correctly informed about cervical cancer and the HPV vaccine by 33 to 66 absolute percentage points. In contrast, the unbalanced leaflet decreased the number of participants who were correctly informed about these facts by 0 to 18 absolute percentage points. Whereas the actual uptake of the HPV vaccination 14 months after the initial study did not differ between the two groups (22% balanced leaflet vs. 23% unbalanced leaflet; p=.93, r=.01), the originally stated intention to have the vaccine reliably predicted the actual vaccination decision for the balanced leaflet group only (concordance between intention and actual uptake: 97% in the balanced leaflet group, rs=.92, p=.00; 60% in the unbalanced leaflet group, rs=.37, p=.08). CONCLUSION: In contrast to a unbalanced leaflet, a balanced leaflet increased people's knowledge of the HPV vaccination, improved perceived risk judgments, and led to an actual vaccination uptake, which first was robustly predicted by people's intention and second did not differ from the uptake in the unbalanced leaflet group. These findings suggest that balanced reporting about HPV vaccination increases informed decisions about whether to be vaccinated and does not undermine actual uptake.


Asunto(s)
Conocimientos, Actitudes y Práctica en Salud , Infecciones por Papillomavirus/prevención & control , Vacunas contra Papillomavirus/uso terapéutico , Educación del Paciente como Asunto , Vacunación/psicología , Toma de Decisiones , Femenino , Alemania , Humanos , Intención , Masculino , Padres/psicología , Encuestas y Cuestionarios , Neoplasias del Cuello Uterino/prevención & control , Neoplasias del Cuello Uterino/virología
19.
Arch Psychiatr Nervenkr (1970) ; 232(1): 39-51, 1982.
Artículo en Alemán | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-7149953

RESUMEN

This study is concerned with the diagnostic process of psychiatrists. Two concepts are investigated; the internalized nosological theory and the psychiatric diagnostic scheme. If patients or diseases are judged on predefined lists of symptoms (e.g. AMDP-list), we assume that judgments are based on the first one. If the psychiatrist, however, is free in the choice of relevant attributes in judging patients or diseases, we assume that his judgments are based on his individual diagnostic scheme. Results show high agreement in internalized nosological theories, but strong individual differences in diagnostic schemes. Interindividual agreement in internalized nosological theories is still greater than intraindividual agreement between diagnostic scheme and nosological theory. This proves that distinguishing the two concepts is meaningful. Structural components of both concepts, e.g., their dimensions, pregnant structures, and their metric, were analyzed by multidimensional scaling. We assume that the psychiatric diagnostic scheme determines the clinical diagnosis in everyday practice, whereas the internalized nosological theory is of importance mainly in research. The differences between both concepts suggest that lists of symptoms are not very helpful in analyzing clinical diagnosis. Thus, in order to achieve greater agreement in diagnosis, further and detailed analysis of individual "implicit" theories which determine the greater part of diagnostic schemes is necessary.


Asunto(s)
Trastornos Mentales/diagnóstico , Alcoholismo/diagnóstico , Trastornos de Ansiedad/diagnóstico , Trastorno Depresivo/diagnóstico , Trastorno Depresivo Mayor/diagnóstico , Diagnóstico Diferencial , Humanos , Histeria/diagnóstico , Trastornos Mentales/psicología , Trastornos del Humor/diagnóstico , Psiquiatría , Teoría Psicológica , Esquizofrenia Hebefrénica/diagnóstico , Esquizofrenia Paranoide/diagnóstico
20.
Arch Psychiatr Nervenkr (1970) ; 232(1): 5-14, 1982.
Artículo en Alemán | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-7149954

RESUMEN

Diagnostic schemes of psychiatrists are explained by two components, a general explicit nosological theory and an individual implicit theory. An experimental study is devoted to the analysis of diagnostic schemes in three groups with different degrees of internalization of explicit nosological theory: (1) a non-psychiatrist group without nosological knowledge (2) a non-psychiatrist group, who obtained nosological knowledge in a 40-min session, and (3) a group of psychiatrists. Four structural components of diagnostic schemes were analyzed: stability, complexity, relevance for therapy of the individual diagnostic scheme, and interindividual homogeneity within groups. The diagnostic schemes of psychiatrists showed no more stability and relevance for therapy than those of group (2), whereas interindividual homogeneity as well as complexity were higher. Results indicate that the diagnostic schemes of psychiatrists are determined to a great extent by individual implicit theories.


Asunto(s)
Trastornos Mentales/diagnóstico , Trastorno Depresivo/diagnóstico , Diagnóstico Diferencial , Humanos , Trastornos Mentales/terapia , Trastornos Neuróticos/diagnóstico , Psiquiatría/educación , Teoría Psicológica , Trastornos Psicofisiológicos/diagnóstico , Trastornos Psicóticos/diagnóstico , Esquizofrenia/diagnóstico
SELECCIÓN DE REFERENCIAS
Detalles de la búsqueda