Your browser doesn't support javascript.
loading
Mostrar: 20 | 50 | 100
Resultados 1 - 16 de 16
Filtrar
Mais filtros











Base de dados
Intervalo de ano de publicação
1.
Am Psychol ; 67(4): 324-5; discussion 325-6, 2012.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22583348

RESUMO

Comments on the original article, "Nonrational processes in ethical decision making" by M. D. Rogerson et al (see record 2011-19198-001). Among the many insightful points made by Rogerson, Gottlieb, Handelsman, Knapp, and Younggren (October 2011) regarding nonrational processes in ethical decision making, one deserves further explication: Many of psychologists' ethical decisions lead to actions done to someone. Unfortunately, frameworks and models of ethical decision making frequently neglect this fact by implying that the decisions happen in the abstract, but in truth, these decisions often affect a specific recipient. Importantly, the characteristics of that specific recipient, especially as perceived by the psychologist, can have a powerful impact on the process of ethical decision making (Caughron et al., 2011). It would be wise to add such a hypothetical to the list of specific questions that Rogerson et al recommended psychologists ask themselves: Would I make the same ethical decision if the person(s) toward whom the decision is directed had different characteristics?


Assuntos
Tomada de Decisões/ética , Emoções/ética , Intuição/ética , Humanos
2.
Am Psychol ; 67(4): 325; discussion 325-6, 2012.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-22583349

RESUMO

Comments on the original article, "Nonrational processes in ethical decision making" by M. D. Rogerson et al (see record 2011-19198-001). The current authors suggest that Rogerson, Gottlieb, Handelsman, Knapp, and Younggren (October 2011) presumed that the only ethical theories available for grounding decision-making models are of the rational, neoliberal variety. Rogerson et al stated, "Contextual, interpersonal, and intuitive factors are inextricably linked and inexorably influential in the process of ethical decision making. Ethical theory would benefit from encompassing these subtle yet powerful forces" (Rogerson et al., 2011, p. 616). They sought to augment these models with a cluster of contextual considerations, appending to them accounts of emotion, context, and intuition. First, notwithstanding the theories attributed to (the caricature of) Kant and his ilk, there are several ethical theories that include an account of what Rogerson et al. (2011) consider to be "nonrational" processes. From feminist theories to narrative ethics, sophisticated contextual theories have been developed and are readily available. Second, we question whether thick contextual considerations can simply be tacked on to extant models of decision making originally built upon a philosophical foundation that assumes a rational, autonomous agent who deliberates independently and logically.


Assuntos
Tomada de Decisões/ética , Emoções/ética , Intuição/ética , Humanos
3.
Am Psychol ; 66(7): 614-23, 2011 Oct.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-21875170

RESUMO

Most current ethical decision-making models provide a logical and reasoned process for making ethical judgments, but these models are empirically unproven and rely upon assumptions of rational, conscious, and quasilegal reasoning. Such models predominate despite the fact that many nonrational factors influence ethical thought and behavior, including context, perceptions, relationships, emotions, and heuristics. For example, a large body of behavioral research has demonstrated the importance of automatic intuitive and affective processes in decision making and judgment. These processes profoundly affect human behavior and lead to systematic biases and departures from normative theories of rationality. Their influence represents an important but largely unrecognized component of ethical decision making. We selectively review this work; provide various illustrations; and make recommendations for scientists, trainers, and practitioners to aid them in integrating the understanding of nonrational processes with ethical decision making.


Assuntos
Tomada de Decisões/ética , Emoções/ética , Intuição/ética , Humanos , Julgamento/ética
4.
Behav Brain Sci ; 33(4): 315-29; discussion 329-65, 2010 Aug.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-20964912

RESUMO

It has often been suggested that people's ordinary capacities for understanding the world make use of much the same methods one might find in a formal scientific investigation. A series of recent experimental results offer a challenge to this widely-held view, suggesting that people's moral judgments can actually influence the intuitions they hold both in folk psychology and in causal cognition. The present target article distinguishes two basic approaches to explaining such effects. One approach would be to say that the relevant competencies are entirely non-moral but that some additional factor (conversational pragmatics, performance error, etc.) then interferes and allows people's moral judgments to affect their intuitions. Another approach would be to say that moral considerations truly do figure in workings of the competencies themselves. I argue that the data available now favor the second of these approaches over the first.


Assuntos
Intuição/ética , Intuição/fisiologia , Julgamento/ética , Julgamento/fisiologia , Comunicação , Humanos , Modelos Psicológicos , Princípios Morais , Ciência/ética
5.
Top Cogn Sci ; 2(3): 511-27, 2010 Jul.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-25163874

RESUMO

Recent research in moral psychology highlights the role of emotion and intuition in moral judgment. In the wake of these findings, the role and significance of moral reasoning remain uncertain. In this article, we distinguish among different kinds of moral reasoning and review evidence suggesting that at least some kinds of moral reasoning play significant roles in moral judgment, including roles in abandoning moral intuitions in the absence of justifying reasons, applying both deontological and utilitarian moral principles, and counteracting automatic tendencies toward bias that would otherwise dominate behavior. We argue that little is known about the psychology of moral reasoning and that it may yet prove to be a potent social force.


Assuntos
Teoria Ética , Intuição/ética , Princípios Morais , Teoria Psicológica , Pensamento/ética , Adulto , Humanos
6.
Monash Bioeth Rev ; 28(1): 4.1-21, 2009 Mar.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-19839275

RESUMO

We consider the current debate between bioconservatives and their chief opponents--whom we dub bioliberals--about the moral acceptability of human enhancement and the policy implications of moral debates about enhancement. We argue that this debate has reached an impasse, largely because bioconservatives hold that we should honour intuitions about the special value of being human, even if we cannot identify reasons to ground those intuitions. We argue that although intuitions are often a reliable guide to belief and action, there are circumstances in which they are not reliable. Intuitions--including intuitions about enhancement--are subject to various cognitive biases rendering them unreliable in some circumstances. We argue that many bioconservative intuitions about enhancement are examples of such unreliable intuitions. Given this, it is unrealistic of bioconservatives to expect others to rely on their unexamined intuitions. Furthermore, refusing to engage in debates about the reasons and values that underpin their intuitions about enhancement will have the effect of making bioconservative voices less relevant in policy debates about enhancement than they would otherwise be.


Assuntos
Melhoramento Biomédico/ética , Dissidências e Disputas , Análise Ética , Política , Avaliação da Tecnologia Biomédica/ética , Atitude Frente a Saúde , Análise Ética/métodos , Medo/ética , Política de Saúde , Humanismo , Humanos , Intuição/ética , Julgamento/ética , Princípios Morais , Filosofia Médica , Preconceito , Valores Sociais , Pensamento/ética , Virtudes
7.
Monash Bioeth Rev ; 28(1): 7.1-17, 2009 Mar.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-19839277

RESUMO

In theory, HREC members should use the ethical guidelines in the National Statement on the Ethical Conduct of Research Involving Humans as the basis for their decisions, and researchers should design their research in accordance with these guidelines. However, very little is known about what researchers and HREC members actually do in practice. In this paper, we report some of the key findings of the study "Human Research Ethics in Practice", a qualitative interview-based study of health researchers and HREC members in Victoria. The findings shed light on how researchers and HREC members conceptualise ethics, how they use the National Statement, and what deliberative strategies they employ to assess the ethical appropriateness of research studies. The findings also reveal differences and similarities between health researchers' and HREC members' perceptions of the roles of HRECs, and point to some sources of misunderstanding and tension. We examine the implications of some of these findings for the ways in which HRECs carry out their task, and research institutions support and promote ethical conduct in research amongst their staff and students. The focus of this study is on health research, but we suggest that the findings are highly relevant to all other research areas where human participants are involved.


Assuntos
Atitude do Pessoal de Saúde , Comitês de Ética em Pesquisa/organização & administração , Ética em Pesquisa , Experimentação Humana , Guias de Prática Clínica como Assunto , Pesquisadores/psicologia , Academias e Institutos/organização & administração , Protocolos Clínicos , Comunicação , Conflito Psicológico , Tomada de Decisões/ética , Revisão Ética/normas , Ética em Pesquisa/educação , Fidelidade a Diretrizes/ética , Conhecimentos, Atitudes e Prática em Saúde , Experimentação Humana/ética , Experimentação Humana/normas , Humanos , Imaginação/ética , Intuição/ética , Objetivos Organizacionais , Ética Baseada em Princípios , Pesquisa Qualitativa , Pesquisadores/educação , Inquéritos e Questionários , Pensamento/ética , Vitória
8.
Bioethics ; 23(5): 274-90, 2009 Jun.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-19076124

RESUMO

According to what we call the Principle of Procreative Beneficence (PB),couples who decide to have a child have a significant moral reason to select the child who, given his or her genetic endowment, can be expected to enjoy the most well-being. In the first part of this paper, we introduce PB,explain its content, grounds, and implications, and defend it against various objections. In the second part, we argue that PB is superior to competing principles of procreative selection such as that of procreative autonomy.In the third part of the paper, we consider the relation between PB and disability. We develop a revisionary account of disability, in which disability is a species of instrumental badness that is context- and person-relative.Although PB instructs us to aim to reduce disability in future children whenever possible, it does not privilege the normal. What matters is not whether future children meet certain biological or statistical norms, but what level of well-being they can be expected to have.


Assuntos
Crianças com Deficiência , Obrigações Morais , Qualidade de Vida , Reprodução/ética , Beneficência , Criança , Comportamento de Escolha/ética , Teoria da Decisão , Dissidências e Disputas , Análise Ética , Teoria Ética , Eugenia (Ciência) , Fertilização in vitro/ética , Testes Genéticos/ética , Humanos , Intuição/ética , Motivação , Pais/psicologia , Autonomia Pessoal , Cuidado Pré-Concepcional/ética , Diagnóstico Pré-Implantação/ética , Diagnóstico Pré-Natal/ética
9.
Bioethics ; 23(5): 265-73, 2009 Jun.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-18477055

RESUMO

The claim that we have a moral obligation, where a choice can be made, to bring to birth the 'best' child possible, has been highly controversial for a number of decades. More recently Savulescu has labelled this claim the Principle of Procreative Beneficence. It has been argued that this Principle is problematic in both its reasoning and its implications, most notably in that it places lower moral value on the disabled. Relentless criticism of this proposed moral obligation, however, has been unable, thus far, to discredit this Principle convincingly and as a result its influence shows no sign of abating. I will argue that while criticisms of the implications and detail of the reasoning behind it are well founded, they are unlikely to produce an argument that will ultimately discredit the obligation that the Principle of Procreative Beneficence represents. I believe that what is needed finally and convincingly to reveal the fallacy of this Principle is a critique of its ultimate theoretical foundation, the notion of impersonal harm. In this paper I argue that while the notion of impersonal harm is intuitively very appealing, its plausibility is based entirely on this intuitive appeal and not on sound moral reasoning. I show that there is another plausible explanation for our intuitive response and I believe that this, in conjunction with the other theoretical criticisms that I and others have levelled at this Principle, shows that the Principle of Procreative Beneficence should be rejected.


Assuntos
Beneficência , Crianças com Deficiência , Teoria Ética , Obrigações Morais , Reprodução/ética , Criança , Comportamento de Escolha/ética , Dissidências e Disputas , Análise Ética , Eugenia (Ciência) , Fertilização in vitro/ética , Testes Genéticos/ética , Política de Saúde , Humanos , Intuição/ética , Lógica , Autonomia Pessoal , Assunção de Riscos , Valor da Vida , Direito de não Nascer/ética
10.
Bioethics ; 23(5): 291-9, 2009 Jun.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-18445093

RESUMO

Advances in reproductive technologies - in particular in genetic screening and selection - have occasioned renewed interest in the moral justifiability of the reasons that motivate the decision to have a child. The capacity to select for desired blood and tissue compatibilities has led to the much discussed 'saviour sibling' cases in which parents seek to 'have one child to save another'. Heightened interest in procreative reasons is to be welcomed, since it prompts a more general philosophical interrogation of the grounds for moral appraisal of reasons-to-parent, and of the extent to which such reasons are relevant to the moral assessment of procreation itself. I start by rejecting the idea that we can use a distinction between 'other-regarding' and 'future-child-regarding' reasons as a basis on which to distinguish good from bad procreative reasons. I then offer and evaluate three potential grounds for elucidating and establishing a relationship between procreative motivation and the rightness/wrongness of procreative conduct: the predictiveness, the verdictiveness, and the expressiveness of procreative reasons.


Assuntos
Obrigações Morais , Motivação , Pais/psicologia , Reprodução/ética , Transplante de Medula Óssea/ética , Criança , Defesa da Criança e do Adolescente/ética , Transplante de Células-Tronco de Sangue do Cordão Umbilical/ética , Tomada de Decisões/ética , Dissidências e Disputas , Análise Ética , Teoria Ética , Fertilização in vitro/ética , Teste de Histocompatibilidade/ética , Humanos , Intuição/ética , Diagnóstico Pré-Implantação/ética , Irmãos , Justiça Social , Valores Sociais
11.
Cogn Affect Behav Neurosci ; 8(4): 390-401, 2008 Dec.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-19033237

RESUMO

What decisions should we make? Moral values, rules, and virtues provide standards for morally acceptable decisions, without prescribing how we should reach them. However, moral theories do assume that we are, at least in principle, capable of making the right decisions. Consequently, an empirical investigation of the methods and resources we use for making moral decisions becomes relevant. We consider theoretical parallels of economic decision theory and moral utilitarianism and suggest that moral decision making may tap into mechanisms and processes that have originally evolved for nonmoral decision making. For example, the computation of reward value occurs through the combination of probability and magnitude; similar computation might also be used for determining utilitarian moral value. Both nonmoral and moral decisions may resort to intuitions and heuristics. Learning mechanisms implicated in the assignment of reward value to stimuli, actions, and outcomes may also enable us to determine moral value and assign it to stimuli, actions, and outcomes. In conclusion, we suggest that moral capabilities can employ and benefit from a variety of nonmoral decision-making and learning mechanisms.


Assuntos
Tomada de Decisões/ética , Princípios Morais , Comportamento de Escolha/ética , Cognição/ética , Condicionamento Psicológico/ética , Teoria Ética , Humanos , Intuição/ética , Modelos Econômicos , Modelos Psicológicos , Recompensa , Valores Sociais
14.
J Med Ethics ; 33(7): 386-9, 2007 Jul.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-17601864

RESUMO

In an attempt to be rational and objective, and, possibly, to avoid the charge of moral relativism, ethicists seek to categorise and characterise ethical dilemmas. This approach is intended to minimise the effect of the confusing individuality of the context within which ethically challenging problems exist. Despite and I argue partly as a result of this attempt to be rational and objective, even when the logic of the argument is accepted--for example, by healthcare professionals--those same professionals might well respond by stating that the conclusions are unacceptable to them. In this paper, I argue that an interpretative approach to ethical analysis, involving an examination of the ways in which ethical arguments are constructed and shared, can help ethicists to understand the origins of this gap between logic and intuition. I suggest that an argument will be persuasive either if the values underpinning the proposed argument accord with the reader's values and worldview, or if the argument succeeds in persuading the reader to alter these. A failure either to appreciate or to acknowledge those things that give meaning to the lives of all the interested parties will make this objective far harder, if not impossible, to achieve. If, as a consequence, the narratives ethicists use to make their arguments seem to be about people living in different circumstances, and faced with different choices and challenges, from those the readers or listeners consider important or have to face in their own lives, then the argument is unlikely to seem either relevant or applicable to those people. The conclusion offered by the ethicist will be, for that individual, counterintuitive. Abortion, euthanasia and cadaveric organ donation are used as examples to support my argument.


Assuntos
Análise Ética/métodos , Ética Médica , Intuição/ética , Lógica , Aborto Induzido/ética , Eutanásia/ética , Humanos , Princípios Morais , Cuidados Paliativos/ética , Terminologia como Assunto , Obtenção de Tecidos e Órgãos/ética
15.
Theor Med Bioeth ; 28(1): 1-30, 2007.
Artigo em Inglês | MEDLINE | ID: mdl-17347919

RESUMO

Moral decision procedures such as principlism or casuistry require intuition at certain junctures, as when a principle seems indeterminate, or principles conflict, or we wonder which paradigm case is most relevantly similar to the instant case. However, intuitions are widely thought to lack epistemic justification, and many ethicists urge that such decision procedures dispense with intuition in favor of forms of reasoning that provide discursive justification. I argue that discursive justification does not eliminate or minimize the need for intuition, or constrain our intuitions. However, this is not a problem, for intuitions can be justified in easy or obvious cases, and decision procedures should be understood as heuristic devices for reaching judgments about harder cases that approximate the justified intuitions we would have about cases under ideal conditions, where hard cases become easy. Similarly, the forms of reasoning which provide discursive justification help decision procedures perform this heuristic function not by avoiding intuition, but by making such heuristics more accurate. Nonetheless, it is possible to demand too much justification; many clinical ethicists lack the time and philosophical training to reach the more elaborate levels of discursive justification. We should keep moral decision procedures simple and user-friendly so that they will provide what justification can be achieved under clinical conditions, rather than trying to maximize our epistemic justification out of an overstated concern about intuition.


Assuntos
Tomada de Decisões/ética , Eticistas , Intuição/ética , Humanos , Conhecimento , Princípios Morais
SELEÇÃO DE REFERÊNCIAS
DETALHE DA PESQUISA